------------ EH.NET BOOK REVIEW --------------
Published by EH.NET (March 2006)
Mark Skousen, _Vienna and Chicago, Friends or Foes? A Tale of Two
Schools of Free-Market Economics_. Washington: Capital Press, 2005. x
+ 305 pp. $25 (paperback), ISBN: 0-895-26029-8.
Reviewed for EH.NET by Pedro Garcia Duarte, Department of Economics,
Duke University.
Mark Skousen is a professional economist and adjunct professor at
Barnard College, Columbia University. In 1994 he gave an address to
the Mont Pelerin Society entitled "I Like Hayek." Much to his
surprise, his generous comments about Hayek's macroeconomics were not
music to the attendees' ears, most of whom were followers of Milton
Friedman. Skousen then wrote _Vienna and Chicago, Friends or Foes?_
to make sense of his baffling experience.
Hayek was one of the founders and the first president (1947-1960) of
that Society, created to foster market-oriented economic systems and
free societies. Among Mont Pelerin's later presidents were three
Chicago professors: Friedman (1970-1972), George Stigler (1976-1978),
and Gary Becker (1990-1992).
Skousen's main question is why do followers of the Austrian and
Chicago schools disagree so much, given that both are "devout
believers in free markets and free minds" (p. 1)? The author explores
the points of agreement and disagreement between these schools. In
doing so, Skousen argues that these economists have more in common
than not. Moreover, he closes the book defending libertarian ideas
and expressing his belief that the bridge linking Austrian and
Chicago schools, to use his metaphor, is coming down "and integrating
a dynamic prosperous community of scholars in both camps" (p. 291).
Chapters two and three discuss the origins and influences of the two
schools. According to Skousen, "the Austrian and Chicago schools were
born in the midst of crises in economic theory, at times when the
classical laissez-faire model of Adam Smith faced unprecedented
challenges from the critics of capitalism. The Austrians rescued
classical economics from the socialist/Marxist threat in the late
19th century, while the Chicago school countered the Keynesian
challenge of the 20th century" (p. 15).
After this account, the next four chapters address the points of
disagreement: whether theories should or should not be empirically
tested; the concept of the ideal monetary system; the business cycle,
capital theory, and macroeconomic model; and the role of government
in a market economy and other microeconomic issues.
In the last three chapters, Skousen broadens the scope of the book by
contrasting not only each school's view of the great economists, but
also the view each school has of the other (chapter eight), and by
exploring the "faith and reason in capitalism" they share (chapter
nine). The concluding chapter asks "how far is Vienna from Chicago?"
and ponders the future of free-market economics.
It is perhaps less of a commentary on Skousen than on present-day
publishing houses to say that the book has a number of typos,
incomplete reference lists, and missing sources of statements by
other economists and of data used in the text. It also lacks clear
definitions of terms that are open to all manner of interpretation,
as, for instance, "Keynesianism" and "Marxism." Furthermore, chapters
eight and especially nine repeat ideas already presented and do not
seem crucial to the main argument of the book.
To the good, Skousen is very familiar with Austrian and Chicago
school theories. He has "developed close friendships with leaders of
both camps" (p. 8) and his personal correspondence with them enhances
the narrative with their personal accounts of issues dealt with in
the book. This correspondence, together with his familiarity with the
literature and humorous writing style, are the greatest merits of the
book.
Skousen's book can be read in at least two ways. One is as a
libertarian manifesto designed to promote Austrian theory and to
identify ways in which this theory could be more successful than it
currently is. This seems to be Skousen's real agenda, especially in
light of his concluding chapters. On this matter I shall take no
stand.
The other reading is as a historical account of the resemblance and
disparity between Austrian and Chicago schools. Comparing schools of
thought, rather than individuals, as well as exploring their
development appeals to historians.
However, the problem is that Skousen's narrative is not historical.
It is rather a search for the "best" argument about the issues
discussed and the great economists behind them -- on whose shoulders
prominent economists will now stand to look for the truth -- as he
clearly states: "This book will analyze all these issues, deciding
which camp has the most convincing arguments for each" (p. 8). He is
outspoken about his personal biases and opinions (see the section
"the author's biases," p. 12), and he is explicit in attaching his
personal judgment about, among other things, who is the winner in
each of the points of disagreement: he closes chapters four to seven
with an "advantage" to Vienna or to Chicago, a battle won twice by
each of them.
Historians of economics have something to say about the origins of
the Austrian and the Chicago schools, about the mathematization of
neoclassical economics and other issues touched on by Skousen (see
Morgan and Rutherford (1998), Mirowski (2002), Weintraub (2002)). An
historical understanding of these and other topics would prevent the
repetition of inaccurate commonplaces such as Keynes being "the
theoretical spokesman for big government and the Welfare State" (p.
58). Moreover, it would also prevent flimsy assertions such as the
rational expectations theory being a Chicago product (p. 75, 85-86)
(see Sent (2002)).
Furthermore, historical critical reasoning calls for clear
documentation supporting one's claims, and, therefore, prevents a
highly implausible statement (as testified by a retired librarian who
worked at Duke at the time) like: "During [the 1960s], for example,
Duke University library refused to carry [Friedman's] books" (p. 73),
presumably because they were at odds with the orthodoxy of the time.
As Skousen personally informed me, he based that claim on Friedman's
(1998, pp. 340-341) memoirs, which his book fails to reference.
Friedman, for his part, heard of the alleged banning from a letter
written to him by a Duke student. More important than judging its
veracity (which is hard to do) is to appraise its relevance. Duke's
Economics Department at the time was far from being a Keynesian
trench defending orthodoxy against Friedman's ideas.
However, it is important to keep in mind that Skousen wisely titled
the book "a tale [not a history!] of two schools of free-market
economics." In writing a tale one is free of historical accuracy.
Moreover, the opposition tale _versus_ history is appropriate for
delineating the differences between Skousen's and an historian's
perspective. For Skousen, "[s]tudying each school brings new insights
and discoveries into the marketplace of ideas" (p. 247). Surprisingly
for an Austrian follower, this characterization of the "marketplace
of ideas" fails to incorporate time and the structure of production
of ideas in a meaningful way, a task historians of science in
general, and of economics in particular, try to tackle.
References:
Milton and Rose Friedman (1998). _Two Lucky People: Memoirs_,
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Philip Mirowski (2002). _Machine Dreams_. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Mary Morgan and Malcolm Rutherford (1998). "From Interwar Pluralism
to Postwar Neoclassicism." _History of Political Economy_ 30
(supplement).
Esther-Mirjam Sent (2002). "How (not) to Influence People: The
Contrary Tale of John F. Muth." _History of Political Economy_ 34 (2).
E. Roy Weintraub (2002). _How Economics Became a Mathematical
Science_. Durham: Duke University Press.
Pedro Garcia Duarte is a Ph.D. candidate in economics at Duke
University with majors in macroeconomics and the history of economic
thought. He is currently working on the history of modern monetary
economics, with a working paper entitled "A Feasible and Objective
Concept of Optimality: The Quadratic Loss Function and U.S. Monetary
Policy in the 1960s."
Copyright (c) 2006 by EH.Net. All rights reserved. This work may be
copied for non-profit educational uses if proper credit is given to
the author and the list. For other permission, please contact the
EH.Net Administrator ([log in to unmask]; Telephone: 513-529-2229).
Published by EH.Net (March 2006). All EH.Net reviews are archived at
http://www.eh.net/BookReview.
-------------- FOOTER TO EH.NET BOOK REVIEW --------------
EH.Net-Review mailing list
[log in to unmask]
http://eh.net/mailman/listinfo/eh.net-review
|