SHOE Archives

Societies for the History of Economics

SHOE@YORKU.CA

Options: Use Forum View

Use Monospaced Font
Show Text Part by Default
Show All Mail Headers

Message: [<< First] [< Prev] [Next >] [Last >>]
Topic: [<< First] [< Prev] [Next >] [Last >>]
Author: [<< First] [< Prev] [Next >] [Last >>]

Print Reply
Subject:
From:
[log in to unmask] (Ross Emmett)
Date:
Fri Mar 31 17:19:14 2006
Content-Type:
text/plain
Parts/Attachments:
text/plain (335 lines)
----------------- HES POSTING ----------------- 
[Yuval Yonay published this originally as an editorial on the Economics-Sociology list.
Jonothan Mote is to be thanked for passing the editorial on to HES. -- RBE]
 
 
Economic Theory and Reality: A Sociological Perspective on Induction and  
Inference in a Deductive Science 
 
I. Introduction 
 
I see myself as a guest writer in this forum.  Although I have a  
deep-rooted interest in economic sociology and commitment to this field  
(I am even a member of the new section), my main interest is not economic  
sociology per se, but economic knowledge in general and professional  
economists in particular.  Yet I guess that my research about economists,  
past and present, gives me a unique point of view to observe on economic  
sociology and to comment on some of the ongoing debates in this field. 
"Sociology of Economists," as I like to christen my field of interest, is  
not exactly a new sub-discipline.  Although I was happily surprised to  
notice a growing interest in this subject, there is no point in further  
dividing our rich discipline.  "Sociology of economists" is, of course,  
part of the sociology of science, the sociology of knowledge, and the  
sociology of intellectuals, and theoretically there is no need to develop  
special tools to analyze the production and distribution of economic  
knowledge beyond those developed in these fields.  Due to the centrality  
of economic issues in class struggles, in national policy-making, and  
even in general culture and human relations, however, this topic has been  
discussed mostly in the context of ideological and political debates over  
the organization of industrial societies.  Thus, while many scholars have  
commented on the connection between economic doctrines of various kinds  
and economic and political interests, very few have systematically  
studied economic discourse in general, and academic economics in particular. 
Most glaring, I think, was the lack of any serious sociological study of  
the academic arena of economic knowledge production, and this is in spite  
of the far-reaching political implications of the economic theories  
produced by academic economists.  The reason, I think, is that those  
interested in studying ideology had little understanding of the obscure,  
highly-mathematized economic theories of the postwar period.  Marx,  
Weber, and many of our other distinguished classical pioneers read the  
economic treatises of their days with ease.  Their modern  
counterparts-whoever they are-could not master the much more complex,  
ethereal, and specialized thought of economics of the postwar period.   
The critique of economic theory has thus remained on a very superficial  
level without detailed studies and understanding of how economists  
actually worked. 
 
I was lucky enough to be among a small group of people who started  
recently to watch and follow economists more rigorously (e.g., Breslau  
1998; Evans 1999; Fourcade-Gourinchas 1999; Gao 1997; Knorr-Cetina and  
Bruegger 2000).  Having an undergraduate training in economics and an  
avid interest in ideology, it was a natural choice to study economics,  
and the sociology of science was the likely place to search inspiration  
and guidance.  Here another comment is due: why had sociologists of  
science never studied economics? Was it because economics was not a  
science?  For some traditional scholars, the answer might be affirmative;  
for them economics, as well as all the other misleadingly-named social  
sciences, were not perceived as a "real science" due to its apparent  
embeddedness in political and ideological debates and lack of  
"scientific" aloofness.  But for most students of science in recent  
years, the reason was exactly the opposite: seeking to challenge the  
common notion of science as a detached human practice above the mundane  
commotion of politics and commerce, they analyzed the "hard" sciences, to  
show how "soft" even the latter were. 
 
In contrast to what many science fundamentalists think, the new sociology  
of science of the last twenty years is not aimed at debunking science.   
Although challenging previous notions of science as naïve and uncritical,  
the current sociologists of science are actually more interested in  
understanding the real power of science than in discrediting it (see  
Knorr-Cetina 1999; Latour 1999; Pickering 1995).  Yes, scientists have  
power and they often abuse it to advance either their own selfish  
interests or to promote class and national interests. But there is more  
than this in science.  If it were only an ideological tool, it would have  
been redundant in societies soaked with national, ethnocentric,  
religious, and consumerist beliefs.  Science-and technology; the new  
sociology of science cares little for distinguishing between the  
two-offers more: it offers machines, tools, and knowledge that can be  
used to produce more goods, more deadly weapons, and better control of  
public health.  Present-day sociology of science tries to understand what  
is it about science that allows such achievements.  This is an important  
task even for those who would prefer these achievements never to have  
been accomplished. 
 
And what about economics? Does the most powerful economic knowledge-the  
knowledge produced by mainstream economic theorists in the major research  
universities in the United States-work as well as physical, chemical,  
medical, and biological knowledge?  I am not going to commit myself to  
any answer here, but I do wish to offer the new sociology of science's  
approach to this question.  As I said above, sociologists of science seek  
to understand what is the key for the power of science, but they do not  
come with a key formula, the Scientific Method, which guarantees  
science's success.  Finding such a key has been the goal of traditional  
philosophy of science for centuries, but this pursuit has failed to yield  
an agreed upon and widely convincing view (Latour 1999).  Instead  
sociologists of science have found that scientists use myriad techniques  
and methods that consolidate and evolve through continuous struggle and  
contestation.  If science bears palpable fruits-and whether a specific  
field of investigation does or does not yield such fruits is often  
debated by conflicting camps within that field-it is because scientific  
methods are always challenged and changed.  There is never a guarantee  
that all theories, methods, and scientifically produced facts are valid.   
 
On the contrary, it has been shown that scientists themselves challenge  
the validity of previous knowledge and that of rival colleagues.  It is  
argued, however, that this process of permanent challenges and  
contestation increases our ability to understand and control (Latour 1987). 
This conclusion undercuts any pretense of neoclassical mathematical  
economists to be better scientists than institutionalist, ethnographic,  
historical, and non-mathematical Marxian economists, or to have tools  
which are "more scientific" than those used by non-economists (see also  
McCloskey 1998).  My own book, The Struggle over the Soul of Economics  
(Yonay 1998), based on my dissertation at Northwestern, documented how  
several actors in the arena of American economics struggled during the  
1920s and 1930s over the nature of economic science, invoking different  
images of science, having faith in different methods, posing different  
goals for their science, suggesting conflicting interpretations of past  
economists, and arguing over their potential contribution to the society  
at large.  None of the actors during the interwar period actually won,  
and instead, the field was swept by a new group of contenders-Paul  
Samuelson, Kenneth Arrow, and Milton Friedman are the most conspicuous  
among them-who offered a completely different conception of economic  
science.   
 
Thus, my book, together with a few other recent books (Morgan and  
Rutherford 1998; Tabb 1999), shows how much economics changed between the  
prewar and the postwar periods.  In a nutshell, prewar economics was very  
much like what many of us want economic sociology to be.  It included a  
basic price theory that was used as one tool among many, but economists  
also used many more tools including surveys, observation, and historical  
documents.  The development of new empirical studies was the dominant  
trend between the world wars.  In terms of theory and policy, economists  
ranged between extreme free marketeers and firm supporters of pro-labor  
reforms.  In contrast to present-day economists, prewar economists of all  
stripes did not hide behind scientific objectivity but explicitly  
referred to ethical, political, and social values in their arguments.   
Ties between economists and neighboring fields-legal studies, sociology,  
anthropology, philosophy, and psychology-strengthened and promised new  
possibilities for research (Tugwell 1924). 
 
This historical narrative is significant, because it means that  
present-day economics is not a natural outgrowth of past tradition, but  
rather it is the result of a struggle which was decided according to the  
balance of power among those involved, their resources, and their  
strategies.  Critics of the new sociology of science claim that it  
legitimizes any claim to be scientific, thereby threatening the rule of  
reason in science.  Staunch mathematical economists, faithful Marxists,  
and devoted institutionalists are afraid that such "post-modernist" views  
would jeopardize the rational pursuit of the Truth, but amazingly enough,  
their Truth is not the same.  The new sociology of science starts from  
these conflicting views of The Truth and from the attempts to stop the  
pursuit of truths-in the plural-by arguing that a certain such pursuit  
does not conform to one's image of science. 
 
If something should be denounced as unscientific, the sociology of  
science implies, it is the attempt to negate the scientific value of  
other approaches and forcibly impose premature closure of discussion and  
debate.  Yet we know that such a practice is quite common in science.   
Scientists do try to convince their colleagues to accept their  
contributions, and they use their resources to disseminate their ideas by  
appointing their students to key positions, by raising funding to produce  
new and interesting experimental results, and by controlling publication  
spaces.  Such a competitive process is inevitable in the attempt to sort  
bad ideas from good ones, and we would like to hope that it would lead to  
the widespread adoption of a new idea only if there is convincing  
evidence in its favor.  Sometimes, however, unequal distribution of  
resources allows one group of scientists to dominate even if their ideas  
are weak, or, more commonly, to bar other ideas that may complement their  
own. 
 
Is this what happened with postwar economics?  Economists argue over this  
question.  Mainstreamers suggest that they gained dominance, because  
their ideas of how to pursue scientific knowledge of the economy were  
more attractive to all "serious" economists (losing sight of the circular  
reasoning embodied in such an argument, but this is typical to many  
practicing scientists of all sorts), and imply that had other approaches  
offered better ways, they would have survived.  Here I wish to step down  
as a neutral sociologist of economics and re-emerge as an involved  
participant.  While it is not clear what happened after World War II, one  
thing is sure: economists have not made a great discovery, nor have they  
become more successful in predicting economic trends.  But for reasons  
that have yet to be studied, they adopted new tools-mathematical models  
and econometric applications of statistics-and believed that in the  
future these tools would yield far-reaching achievements (just to dispel  
common views, this approach ascended to power despite the objections of  
powerful institutionalist and anti-mathematical neoclassical economists  
in the United States, and of Keynes' own pupils in Britain).  During the  
1950s they managed to push aside other ways of doing economics and  
cleansed the major departments of institutionalists, Marxian, and  
anti-mathematical neoclassicists, and then they used their academic  
standing to take control of more sub-fields-law and economics, labor  
economics, and so forth-and given the US global dominance, to defeat  
other approaches in other parts of the world. 
 
Saying that mathematical economics has not won due to its proved  
scientific superiority does not mean that the triumphant mathematical  
economists have not had significant achievements in understanding various  
aspects of economic life, controlling certain elements of it, or  
contributing insights into other social processes.  From the point of  
view of the new sociology of science it is virtually unimaginable that  
hundreds of intelligent people-committed either to the pursuit of  
knowledge and/or of their own academic standing-would not find  
interesting things to tell us.  The question is what has been lost; what  
other ways to study the economy have been forfeited and what insights  
have therefore never been reached.  A related question is whose goals are  
being served by the currently hegemonic approach, and whose goals are  
not.  The fact that economists do not address the issue we think are most  
important does not mean that they do not succeed in answering other  
people's needs. 
 
The vacuum left by economists in the 1960s and 1970s started to be filled  
very guardedly by neighboring disciplines during the 1980s and  
increasingly in the 1990s.  Psychologists have tested decision making  
experimentally; political scientists have examined relationships between  
various policies and macroeconomic performance; anthropologists have  
examined more rigorously the economic organization of traditional  
societies, and organization theorists studied the actual management of  
big corporations.  Economic sociology is among the more recent tribes to  
encroach on the territories formerly deserted by economists and its goals  
are more sweeping, running from macroeconomic policies and class  
relations to consumer behavior and job search.  That is, perhaps, why  
economic sociologists are more preoccupied with the ties between their  
field and economics.  In a sense, economic sociology is seeking to be  
what economics was until 1945. 
 
What should economic sociology be like?  What methods should be used in  
studying the economy, and what issues should be investigated?  I don't  
believe that philosophers and sociologists of science can answer these  
questions.  The main lesson of the new sociology of science is that there  
are plenty of ways to study the economy, and various ways can yield  
different insights.  Yes, we should search for what is the most promising  
and most important topic to study, and we should search for what are the  
best ways to understand that topic, and once we find these, we should  
convince others.  Thus, the sociology of science tells us that we must  
continue to struggle not only with other disciplines but also among us.   
 
This is not a battle cry.  On the contrary, this is a call for pluralism,  
because the sociology of science also tells us that even when we are  
certain of our choices, we should not think that we have found The  
Truth.  We should therefore keep the door open and listen to others. 
This ethical precept applies also to our relations with economics.  We  
should not shy away from disputes and criticism.  They are not more  
"scientific" then us, and while they have improved some techniques and  
took them to new heights, they have also abandoned a large tract of land,  
and, in this sense, have become less rigorous.  We should therefore not  
try to discredit their approach but instead understand what the  
economists try to do (a project Daniel Breslau and I are engaged in at  
present; see Breslau and Yonay 1999 for a first fruit from that study)  
and then show what is missing in the economists' models.  We should also  
offer arguments about the practical use of our work versus economists'  
work.  Applying the law of diminishing returns, we can say that the  
marginal productivity of adding more marginalist analyses would be rather  
low.  Economic sociologists have many things to study, things which  
economists know nothing about and which are important to our ability to  
understand the economy and use that knowledge to advance social goals;  
the marginal productivity of these new fields should be much higher than  
that of orthodox economics.  We, economic sociologists, should do it  
without any feeling of inferiority and without any need to justify the  
scientific nature of our pursuits.  What to do depends on one's goals and  
values.  It is not a matter of what is scientific, but a question of what  
is more important given one's goals and interests. 
 
But one more comment before I end.  Many sociologists perceive economists  
as the servants of power, and themselves as critics of power.  My study  
of the economic profession taught me, however, to be more careful.   
Unlike what many sociologists think, mathematical economists did not  
simply win because they served big business and conservative government.   
At the late 40s and early 50s, institutionalists were very powerful and  
well represented in many governmental offices and agencies.  Furthermore,  
many pioneering mathematical economists believed that their tools could  
be used by governments to improve economic conditions and prevent  
catastrophes like the Great Depression; their ideas were vehemently  
opposed by business groups and by non-mathematical neoclassical  
economists.  It is only after they had gained hegemony in the American  
academy that they entered the circles of power and gradually became less  
and less inclined to favor government intervention.  The causal  
connection between these two processes has not been studied yet, although  
it is not hard to suggest ideas of how the two processes reinforced each  
other.  In any case, economic sociologists should be warned: gaining more  
attention from policy makers and from the public in general would change  
the internal dynamics of economic sociology, and its relations with the  
powers-that-be,  as well.  
 
II. Bibliography 
 
Breslau, Daniel. 1998. In Search of the Unequivocal: The Political  
Economy of Measurement in U.S. Labor Market Policy. Westport, CT: Praeger. 
 
Breslau, Daniel and Yuval Yonay. 1999. "Beyond Metaphors: Mathematical  
Models in Economics as Empirical Research." Science in Context 12(2): 317-32. 
 
Evans, Robert. 1999. Macro-Economic Forecasting: A Sociological  
Appraisal. London: Routledge. 
 
Fourcade-Gourinchas, Marion Cécile. 1999. The National Trajectories of  
Economic Knowledge: Discipline and Profession in the United States. Ph.D.  
dissertation, Harvard University.  
 
Gao, Bai. 1997. Economic Ideology and Japanese Industrial Policy:  
Developmentalism from 1931 to 1965. New York: Cambridge University Press. 
 
Knorr-Cetina, Karin D. 1999. Epistemic Cultures: How the Sciences Make  
Knowledge. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. 
 
Knorr-Cetina, Karin and Urs Bruegger. 2000. "The Market as an Object of  
Attachment: Exploring Postsocial Relations in Financial Markets."  
Canadian Journal of Sociology 25(2). 
 
Latour, Bruno. 1987. Science in Action. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. 
 
---. 1999. Pandora's Hope: Essays on the Reality of Science Studies.  
Cambridge: Harvard University Press. 
 
McCloskey, Deirdre N. 1998. The Rhetoric of Economics. 2nd ed. Madison:  
The University of Wisconsin Press. 
 
Morgan, Mary S. and Malcolm Rutherford (eds.). 1998. From Interwar  
Pluralism to Postwar Neoclassicism: Annual Supplement to Volume 30,  
History of Political economy. Duke University Press.  
 
Pickering, Andrew. 1995. The Mangle of Practice. Chicago: University of  
Chicago Press. 
 
Tabb, William. 1999. Reconstructing Political Economy: The Great Divide  
in Economic Thought. London: Routledge. 
 
Tugwell, Rexford G. (ed.). The Trend of Economics. New York: A. A. Knoff. 
 
Yonay, Yuval P. 1998. The Struggle over the Soul of Economics:  
Institutionalist and Neoclassical Economists in America between the Wars.  
Princeton: Princeton University Press. 
 
 
------------ FOOTER TO HES POSTING ------------ 
For information, send the message "info HES" to [log in to unmask] 

ATOM RSS1 RSS2