----------------- HES POSTING -----------------
Published by EH.NET (April 2004)
Heino H. Nau and Bertram Schefold, editors, _The Historicity of Economics:
Continuities and Discontinuities of Historical Thought in 19th and 20th
Century Economics_. Berlin and Heidelberg: Springer, 2002. vii + 245 pp.
$79.95 or £54 (hardcover), ISBN: 3-540-42765-1.
Reviewed for EH.NET by Roberto Romani, Faculty of Political Sciences,
University of Teramo, Italy.
This book deals with the legacies that historical political economies since Schmoller
have left behind them. As Bertram Schefold writes, this collection of six conference
papers addresses "the causes and consequences of adopting a historical perspective in
economics." The underlying assumption is that the historical perspective "is like looking
through a kaleidoscope": a slight turn and the image begins to change, a larger turn and a
new image arises, "but some principle of symmetry persists" (p. vii). The book combines
chapters placing historical economics in historical context with chapters pointing to the
validity of historical concepts and viewpoints for the economists of today. At least one
extensive commentary is appended to each contribution. As regards the editors'
institutional affiliations, Schefold is a full professor of economics at the Goethe
University in Frankfurt am Main, Germany, and Heino Heinrich Nau works at the same
university as an assistant professor.
Nau's introduction establishes a link between the nineteenth-century
Historical School of Economics and New Institutional Economics, on the
grounds of a common concern with institutions and path dependency. Nau's
intention is to show that "major research interests of Historical Economics
are once more relevant in modern economics" (p.3). Nau's twofold goal is to
provide a fresher image of Schmoller's Historical School, on the one hand,
and to add to the store of critical arguments against the neoclassical
paradigm, on the other. Nau uses a broad brush to articulate his view of
the Historical School as a forerunner of new institutional economics. Some
major new institutionalists' themes are surveyed but precise references to
historical economists' texts are scanty.
Of the two chapters concerning the German Historical School neither is
completely original. Heath Pearson rehearses his view that there was no
such thing as a "German Historical School."[1] Pearson puts in its place a
group of economists -- ranging from Roscher and Schmoller to Schäffle,
Wagner, and Sombart -- who attempted to fulfil the promise of a
"comparative" (that is empirical and fact-based) psychology as the core of
comparative economics. Knut Borchardt, for whom "a strong or well defined
connection between psychology and economics" did not exist (p. 48), rejects
Pearson's hypothesis. Karl Häuser defends the use of the label "German
Historical School," especially because of the differences existing between
the German and the non-German unorthodox political economies in the final
decades of the nineteenth century. The former was shaped by "a special
emanation of economics in the tradition of historism" (p. 55).
The following essay by David Lindenfeld is an outline of part of his book
on the institutional framework within which nineteenth-century German
political economy functioned.[2] In Lindenfeld's view, "the emergence of
economics in Germany as a research program was shaped to a great extent by
the pedagogical environment in which it grew" (p. 57). History and
economics, Lindenfeld argues, were linked in many ways in German curricula,
and often individuals taught both. In his commentary, Erik Grimmer-Solem
points to the need to explore not only continuities in the
_Staatswissenschaften_ tradition but also changes. Among these, he notes
the consequences of the generation gap between, say, Schmoller and Roscher,
and of the move of the _Staatswissenschaften_ from the law to the
philosophical faculty. A further commentary by Pearson questions the idea,
which he ascribes to Lindenfeld, that interdisciplinary cross-fertilization
was peculiar to Germany before the "breakthrough" in disciplinary
specialization occurring at the turn of the century.
Like Pearson and Lindenfeld, Geoffrey Hodgson summarizes arguments exposed
by him in greater detail elsewhere. His contribution surveys "historical
specificity" in the writings of "old" American institutionalists.
"Historical specificity" is the idea that "different socio-economic
phenomena require theories that are in some respects different from each
other" (p. 93). Hodgson clearly supports the view that "with diverse,
complex phenomena, there are limits to explanatory unification" (p. 93),
but no further details are given about the role and importance of
"historical specificity." In commenting on the chapter, Helge Peukert
points to this deficiency. Hodgson considers various issues related to
"historical specificity," like habits and knowledge in economic life,
Darwinian evolution, instinct psychology, ideal type theories, the role of
customs and incentives, and economic stages. As a result his contribution
lacks a recognizable focus.
Almost incidentally, Peukert reminds the reader that old institutionalism
"was engaged in the political battles of its time" (p. 128) -- as were the
European historical schools. This is a platitude perhaps, but one which is
often forgotten by critics of mainstream economics writing in the
historical and institutional traditions. They fail to take into account the
well established connection between those traditions and social and
political reform. One wonders whether not only institutions and history
matter, as the authors of this book keep repeating, but also political
orientations do. It is a fact that, besides the universal validity of its
laws, value neutrality is the most effective guarantee of the scientific
character of neoclassical economics. Historical and institutional
economics, on the other hand, are value laden, at least in origin, and the
model of scientificity they intended to attain was somehow different. Peter
Koslowski does not ignore this question, since his chapter is unequivocal
about the necessity of a "normative" political economy. He argues in favor
of a "theory of ethical economy as a cultural, ethical, and historical
economics," basing his proposal chiefly on Schmoller. However, Koslowski
criticizes Schmoller's "ethical relativism." Matthias Lutz-Bachmann
comments on the difficulties involved in any "integration" of the normative
with the empirical approach.
The title of Richard Swedberg's paper is "What Can New Economic Sociology
Learn from the Historical School, Especially Max Weber?" Drawing on
previous writings of his, Swedberg proposes to replace Granovetter's
"embeddedness" with Weber's concept of social action centered on the
element of "orientation to others." Swedberg puts to use Weber's conceptual
precision to seek a fresh perspective on new economic sociology. In
particular, Weber was way ahead of new economic sociology, Swedberg
contends, with reference to the conceptualization of capitalism, the
subjective method of analysis (_Verstehen_), the role of power structures
in the economy, and the application of counterfactuals. Philippe Steiner's
commentary emphasizes the potential usefulness of Weber's "historicity" to
economic sociology.
The collection concludes with an essay by Rainer Klump on the place and
role of "culturally determined parameters" in utility functions, both
individual and collective. Vitantonio Gioia questions Klump's view that
classical political economy had rejected the intrusion of culture into
economics in the same way as marginalism did. According to Gioia, Smith and
J. S. Mill effectively addressed the problem of how culture affects the
behavior of economic man, so that a proper break occurred only with the
marginalistic revolution. Neoclassical maximizers entail a "removal of
socio-cultural conditionings" (p. 233). This is why, continues Gioia, "the
possibility of producing eclectic syntheses between theories grounded on
different visions of the economic agent is very limited" (p. 235).
1. See H. Pearson, "Was There Really a German Historical School of
Economics?" _History of Political Economy_, 31 (1999), pp. 547-62. 2. See
D. Lindenfeld, _The Practical Imagination: The German Sciences of State in
the Nineteenth Century_, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1997.
Roberto Romani works as a researcher at the University of Teramo, Italy. He is the author
of _National Character and Public Spirit in Britain and France, 1750-1914_, Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press, 2002. He also authored, with E. Grimmer-Solem, "In Search of
Full Empirical Reality: Historical Political Economy, 1870-1900," _European Journal of the
History of Economic Thought_, 6 (1999), pp. 333-64, and "The Historical School, 1870-1900:
A Cross-National Reassessment," _History of European Ideas_, 24 (1998), pp. 267-99.
Copyright (c) 2004 by EH.Net. All rights reserved. This work may be copied
for non-profit educational uses if proper credit is given to the author and
the list. For other permission, please contact the EH.Net Administrator
([log in to unmask]; Telephone: 513-529-2229). Published by EH.Net (April
2004). All EH.Net reviews are archived at http://www.eh.net/BookReview.
------------ FOOTER TO HES POSTING ------------
For information, send the message "info HES" to [log in to unmask]
|