SHOE Archives

Societies for the History of Economics

SHOE@YORKU.CA

Options: Use Forum View

Use Monospaced Font
Show Text Part by Default
Show All Mail Headers

Message: [<< First] [< Prev] [Next >] [Last >>]
Topic: [<< First] [< Prev] [Next >] [Last >>]
Author: [<< First] [< Prev] [Next >] [Last >>]

Print Reply
Subject:
From:
[log in to unmask] (Ross B. Emmett)
Date:
Fri Mar 31 17:19:08 2006
Content-Type:
text/plain
Parts/Attachments:
text/plain (254 lines)
======================= HES POSTING ================= 
 
"Common Sense Economics" 
 
Flavio Comim 
Cambridge University 
 
Economics has been accused of being too abstract, irrelevant, unrealistic 
and of employing a wrong deductivist ontology. I would rather blame it, 
when practised under the rules of the `formalist revolution', for 
distancing itself from common sense - this seldom understood notion 
responsible for the ways in which we, as social beings, conceive of 
reality. 
 
The `formalist revolution', the `engine' of economic theorisation since 
the beginning of the 1950s, has become the absolute approach in 
economics. It has determined overwhelmingly the methods, techniques, 
contents and results of the discipline. It also implies an adoption of 
mathematical values, a scientistic style and a maintenance of the 
traditional neoclassical core of economic theory. Attempts at criticising 
the theoretical aspects of the `formalist revolution' have often been 
unsuccessful due to their dismissive attitude to economists' practices, 
practices which have provided posts, papers and academic prestige for 
economists. I agree with Debreu's (1986, 1991) accounts of the `formalist 
revolution' having produced a `rapid contemporary construction of 
economic theory' which has `profoundly transformed our profession'. I 
also agree with him that the `formalist revolution' is not particularly 
vulnerable in its theoretical aspects. I do, however, have strong doubts 
about the success of the practical aspects of this style of theorising. 
 
The extensive mathematisation of economics has produced a `fossilisation' 
(see Woo, 1986) of economic concepts which has, through a provision of 
ready-made and general answers, undermined the economists's practical 
abilities to exercise judgement, to use discretionary reasoning and to 
discern complex phenomena. The rigid theoretical structures developed 
through `fossilisation' have fostered abstractions but not the 
economists's capacity to abstract. As a result, `reality' has become very 
difficult to introduce into the core structure of theories. The aspects 
of reality that are little or non-formalisable are practically ignored by 
economic theories. Moreover, as extra- empirical criteria became more 
important to the development of theories, formal reconstitution of old 
theories became the aim of much of new theorising. 
 
Fossilised theories do not provide good practical guidance. With 
economists' expressible intuition about economic phenomena restricted to 
the limit of what is expressible mathematically, attempts at linking 
economics to `reality' face the mismatch and credibility problems. In 
general lines, the mismatch problem consists of i) the economists's 
struggles to adapt their empirical, fuzzy and commonsensical ideas about 
the world they live in to the rigid theoretical predicates of their 
axiomatised theories and ii) the economists's difficulties to falsify 
(or, if nothing more, test empirically) their theories, for instance with 
`data-mining' routines and ad hoc apriorisms. Because of the ways in 
which empirical results are obtained, how arbitrary are the provisos 
needed to make theoretical results applicable, and what these results 
supposedly represent, economists and the general public tend to regard 
them with scepticism, giving rise to the credibility problem. Thus, as 
far as the practical aspects of the `formalist revolution' are concerned, 
economists build precise theories and models, but do not seem to have 
much confidence in them once they look incomplete or inapplicable in 
relation to reality. 
 
The credibility of economic knowledge may rest on its emulation of the 
methods used in natural sciences, on its predictive features or merely on 
its use of mathematics. However, credibility is ultimately based on some 
correspondence between scientific statements and the complex, incomplete 
and intertwined elements which constitute our conception of reality. This 
means that the validation of models is not a mechanical process, based 
purely on formal elements, but on a social process, involving scientists' 
judgements, experiences and their capacity to persuade. Persuasion may be 
explained by the historical processes of paradigm formation and the 
derived standards of communication and consensuality. Nevertheless, there 
is a wide and important region of agreement constituted by the common 
sense cognition of the real world, of everyday things. This is based on 
individuals' faculties of pattern recognition which express their 
awareness of their social experience of the world's significant features. 
 
People's sense of reality is provided by their common sense. By common 
sense I understand a complex set of beliefs and propositions about 
fundamental features of the world that we assume in whatever we do in 
ordinary life. It relies on individuals' socialisation and social 
practices as a source of cognition and entails a learning process. The 
empirical reality of common sense consists of qualified objects and the 
process of developing common sense is the process of qualification of 
experience. Thus, from their social experience people learn many things, 
for example, that factual statements are contingently true, in the sense 
that they may change according to the circumstances [for more on this see 
Grave (1972), Ayer (1969) and Bharadwaja (1977)]. It is precisely because 
of its flexibility as a body of practical knowledge that common sense is 
considered here as people's notion of reality. They also learn that in 
order to understand reality we need to individuate it according to its 
basic elements. Hollis (1994: 237) has observed that "Westerners organise 
their experience and make sense of it by means of categories of space, 
time, causation, number, agency and persons". As a result, common sense 
is articulated through many subtle modes of reasoning used by individuals 
in their complex interactions with reality. 
 
Common sense provides a critical foundation for the assessment of our 
experiences. As Anderson (1993: 104) has pointed out, "Commonsense 
critical practices can objectively endorse the intuitions they employ 
because they already contain methods for criticising what people take to 
be reasons and for introducing novel reasons in normative discussions". 
For instance, Sen's ethical considerations which affect actual human 
behaviour, Simon's concept of procedural rationality, Kahneman's 
criterion of substantive rationality, Mortimore's ordinary sense of 
rational action and Schutz's weak rationality are all examples of 
economists' critical use of common sense as a foundation for economic 
analysis. 
 
I have mentioned many times the word reality, but what is reality all 
about? Perhaps we should read Tony Lawson's new book or attend this 
month's conference at the Erasmus Institute of Philosophy and Economics 
in order to find out what reality means for economists and how their 
theories should relate to it. Or, we could first turn to the History of 
Economic Thought and look for the critical common sense practices of 
economists concerned with reality.  
 
There is much to be learned, for instance, from Adam Smith's conceptual 
building based on the reality of his time, Stuart Mill's theory-practice 
distinction, Philip Wicksteed's Aristotelian reading of the marginal 
principle, Alfred Marshall's appeal to ceteris paribus as a device used 
in ordinary thinking, Maynard Keynes's notion of vagueness and Kaldor's 
principle of stylised facts, to mention just a few. There is also much to 
be learned from Geoff Harcourt's `horses for courses' approach. Common 
sense is the veiled, unexplained and taken for granted principle behind 
these contributions. An explicit discussion of the role of common sense 
in economic theory may contribute to an understanding of the practical 
aspects neglected by the `formalist revolution' and help us to build up 
more reliable knowledge in our discipline. 
 
Yes, you may say, but how are we to build scientific economic theories 
based on common sense? [This point was fastened upon by both Arthur 
Diamond and Wade Hands in the discussion of the paper (On the Concept of 
Common Sense Economics) that I presented last summer at the HES meeting 
in Charleston.] The answer is to structure economic explanation in a way 
similar to the manner in which we describe objects and propositions in 
the real world, that is, in spatio-temporal frameworks which respect the 
existence of particular realities. A concrete common sense research 
agenda could entail three lines of action: the establishment of common 
sense rules of thumb based on economists's critical discussions; the 
development of methods following a social ontology; and the study of the 
History of Economic Thought. These devices could be used by economists to 
make a bridge between theories' universality and their practical aspects. 
A preliminary list of common sense methodological rules of thumb, 
provided by the critical reflections on the formalist revolution, would 
include: 1) use of introspection and social experiences as the 
starting-point of analysis; 2) starting theoretical analysis from a 
conceptual inquiry, so that the limits, restrictions and particularities 
of the study are clearly stated and known with confidence; 3) choose the 
technique, and the level of abstraction (and reduction) in the theorising 
process, according to the questions being asked; 4) give epistemic 
priority to particular situations over general ones; 5) aim for accuracy 
of the models (in terms of empirical relevance) and not formalist 
precision; 6) employment, whenever possible, of more concrete categories, 
facilitating the task of applying theory; 7) emphasis on history and 
institutional context; and 8) use of mathematics as a tool, not as an end 
in itself. 
 
I propose that instead of adopting the scientific strategy of looking for 
global attractors in economic systems, we should look for local 
attractors and their patterns of change. Instead of assuming that 
behavioural patterns are homogeneous, I propose that we should 
individuate each pattern or group of patterns and articulate them. 
Instead of developing models based on an optimal representative agent, I 
propose that we should include a diversity of economic agents pursuing 
different aims using different strategies. Instead of analysing 
decision-making based on theoretical uniform guidelines, I propose that 
we take into account the practical and axiological aspects of rationality 
involved in each process of decision-making. Instead of presupposing 
logical, reversible structures, I propose that we should work with a 
concept of irreversibility of economic structures and with 
decision-making which emphasises the causes of the change and evolution 
of systems rather than their equilibrium properties. Finally, I propose 
that we organise the relevant features or aspects of reality through 
concepts that represent the idea of cluster, serving the purpose of 
individuating reality. Two organising concepts that would do this job are 
the concepts of history (see Hayes, 1985) and schemata (see Martin, 
1994). 
 
What I have called `Common Sense Economics' (CSE) is an argument for a 
more realistic economics that is developed at three levels: the 
methodological level, the level of History of Economic Thought and the 
applied or empirical level. From the methodological level, I define CSE 
as an attempt to develop methods close (and logically similar) to the 
social realities they refer to. From the HET perspective, I define CSE as 
a tacit tradition in economics which stresses the use of commonsensical 
categories with regard to the aims and ways of theorising. From the 
applied level, I define CSE as an strategy for a more reliable 
theorisation in economics. 
 
To conclude, I would like to make a mention of the many criticisms of 
mainstream economics that have proposed alternative methodological 
approaches for our discipline, i.e. Post-Keynesians, Methodological 
Pluralists, Feminist Economists, Institutionalists, Critical Realists and 
supporters of McCloskey's Rethorics of Economics, to name just a few. 
However, because each stream defines its own qualities and emphasises its 
differences from the others, there has been no fruitful dialogue among 
alternative approaches. There is no unified approach able to question the 
usefulness of contemporary economics, and consequently there is no real 
challenge to mainstream economics. The only constructive approach is one 
that emphasises the similarities in the alternatives proposed, not their 
differences. 
 
The common ground in these alternative approaches is their underlying 
concept of reality. The reality they appeal to in their theories is the 
reality perceived through their common sense. This common base could 
provide the consensus needed for the different streams to be compatible. 
There is an urgent need to reach consensus among the profession on new 
practical guidelines to be followed in order to make economics a more 
reliable discipline. Common Sense Economics provides the framework needed 
to assemble the alternative streams into a unified effort to restructure 
economics. 
 
 
References 
 
ANDERSON, E. (1993) Value in Ethics and Economics. Cambridge and London:  
Harvard University Press. 
 
AYER, A. (1969) Metaphysics and Common Sense. London: MacMillan Press. 
 
BHARADWAJA, S. (1977) Philosophy of Common Sense. New Delhi: National  
Publishing House. 
 
COOLEY, T. and LEROY, S. (1981) "Identification and Estimation of Money  
Demand", American Economic Review 71 (December): 825-43. 
 
DEBREU, G. (1986) "Theoretic Models: Mathematical Form and Economic  
Content". Econometrica 54 (November): 1259-70. 
 
DEBREU, G. (1991) "The Mathematization of Economic Theory". The American  
Economic Review 81 (March): 1-7. 
 
GRAVE, S. (1972) "Common Sense". In: EDWARDS, P. (ed.) The Encyclopedia of  
Philosophy, vol. 1, pp. 155-60. New York: MacMillan Press 
 
HAYES, P. (1985) "The Second Naive Physics Manifesto". In: HOBBS, J. and  
MOORE, R., Formal Theories of the Commonsense World. Ablex  
Publishing Corporation. 
 
HOLLIS, M. (1994) The Philosophy of Social Science: an introduction.  
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 
 
LAWSON, T. (1997) Economics and Reality. London: Routledge. 
 
MARTIN, B. (1994) "The Schema". In: COWAN, G., PINES, D. and MELTZER, D.  
(eds) Complexity: Metaphors, Models, and Reality, 263-85. Proceedings  
Vol. XIX, Santa Fe Institute. Addison Wesley. 
 
WOO, H. (1986) What's Wrong with Formalization in Economics? Hong Kong: 
Victoria Press.  
============ FOOTER TO HES POSTING ============ 
For information, send the message "info HES" to [log in to unmask] 

ATOM RSS1 RSS2