SHOE Archives

Societies for the History of Economics

SHOE@YORKU.CA

Options: Use Forum View

Use Monospaced Font
Show Text Part by Default
Show All Mail Headers

Message: [<< First] [< Prev] [Next >] [Last >>]
Topic: [<< First] [< Prev] [Next >] [Last >>]
Author: [<< First] [< Prev] [Next >] [Last >>]

Print Reply
Subject:
From:
[log in to unmask] (Ross Emmett)
Date:
Fri Mar 31 17:18:21 2006
Content-Type:
text/plain
Parts/Attachments:
text/plain (264 lines)
Published by EH.NET (April 2004) 
 
Kenneth R. Hoover, _Economics as Ideology: Keynes, Laski, Hayek, and the 
Creation of Contemporary Politics_.  Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 
2003. xv + 329 pp. $27.95 (paper), ISBN: 0-7425-3113-9. 
 
Reviewed for EH.NET by Steven Horwitz, Department of Economics, St. 
Lawrence University. 
 
 Attempting to weave together intellectual and personal biographies of more than one great
thinker is a daunting enough task, but when the attempt includes three of the towering
figures in twentieth-century political economy, the task is that much more difficult.
Kenneth Hoover, a political scientist at Western Washington University, takes on this
high-degree-of-difficulty act of authorship in his book on Keynes, Laski, and Hayek, and
is quite successful, at least for the first two-thirds of the book.  For the first eight
chapters, Hoover does a marvelous job in interweaving the ideas and lives of these three
men by setting them against the great events of their time.  Rather than offer us
sequential biographies of each, Hoover organizes his chapters by decades and events, and
then demonstrates how each thinker's life and ideas were affected by the events of their
times.  The result in those eight chapters is a rich portrait of the politics and
intellectual life of Great Britain (and to a lesser extent, the United States) during the
formative events of the century, and these chapters serve as a good, though flawed,
general introduction to the ideas of these three men.
 
Hoover's analytical framework is what he terms "identity relations 
analysis," where an individual's identity is not determined by fixed 
characteristics such as gender, nor is it solely about one's "personal 
characteristics, nor an artifact of an exercise of power nor of social 
construction, but a dynamic set of relations in which both self and society 
play an inescapable role" (p. 6).  Hoover is particularly interested in the 
ways in which these identity relations link to the formation of ideologies. 
One way of capturing the perspective he brings is his interest in how the 
events of one's personal life and social context help to create one's 
identity and then how one's ideological views in turn reflect that 
understanding of one's identity.  That is, how did the lives and contexts 
of these three great thinkers affect the ideas that have become associated 
with them both during their lives and after?  In Hoover's own statement of 
this perspective, there is not a simple, direct line between one's "inner 
self" and one's ideological perspective, e.g., it is not the case that we 
adopt particular views because we are the product of divorced parents, or 
because we clamored for attention among numerous siblings.  It is a more 
complex interplay of history, psychology, and social relationships. 
 
His account of Keynes is fairly standard in seeing Keynes's privileged 
upbringing and association with the Bloomsbury crowd as central to his 
identity formation and the ideas that emerged from it.  Keynes is the hero 
of this story, it should be noted, with his, in Hoover's view, more 
pragmatic commitment to the importance of democratic processes and 
intellectually-oriented leadership and expertise being preferred to Laski's 
and Hayek's more rigid ideological stances to Keynes's left and right 
respectively.  Keynes's background is linked to his rejection of accepted 
social norms and ideas, and his willingness to "tinker" with those through 
various processes of trial and error.  Hoover also sees Keynes's background 
and eventual rise through the ranks of British intellectual and political 
circles as forcing him to both trim off any ideological excesses and 
maintain a willingness to shift ideas and strategies as the demands on him 
changed.  Hoover sees his ongoing shifts in position as evidence of 
discovery and learning (though he is notably unwilling to extend the same 
charitable interpretation to Laski and Hayek), and evidence of his ultimate 
trust in the morality of the leadership, encapsulated in Keynes's famous 
quip about the acceptability of "dangerous acts" in communities that "think 
and feel rightly" as well as the similar idea in his comments on Hayek's 
_Road to Serfdom_ about the danger being lessened with "right-minded" 
people making policy. 
 
Hoover's take on Laski centers around Laski's rebellion against both his 
family and the capitalist structure of society.  Laski's marriage to Frida 
Kerry was a slap in the face of his Jewish family and their expectations of 
him and his future.  Their relationship, in Hoover's view, both symbolized 
Laski's willingness to challenge radically the old order, and also provided 
him with the intellectual and personal companionship that made his 
productive career possible.  His sympathies to socialism were further 
rebellion against his family background from the merchant class of 
Manchester.  His well-to-do upbringing also enabled him to get the 
"cultural tools" necessary to engage in the battle of ideas in the decades 
to follow. These tools and the motivation coming out of his family 
circumstances help to create Laski's position as radical critic of the 
existing economic order, both through the world of ideas and through his 
political and social activism.  In addition, the variety of communities 
with which Laski identified, from his Judaism to his upbringing in 
Manchester to the academic communities of the U.S. and U.K. to his work 
with union organizers, help to explain his "initially pluralist approach to 
politics" (p. 226). 
 
Interestingly, Hoover's interpretation of Hayek parallels Laski's in some 
important respects.  Hayek, as the child of a family of academics and 
intellectuals and coming to adulthood during World War I, would 
understandably be attracted to the world of ideas and to saving 
civilization from what appeared to be forces gathered against it early in 
the century. Not originally seeing himself as a radical or intellectual 
rebel, it would be his contact with von Mises and the rise of Soviet Russia 
that would push Hayek toward the political views that are now so tightly 
associated with him.  But as Hoover rightly notes, Hayek wrote little of 
broader political concerns in the 1920s and 30s, sticking with his more 
technical work in economics in his battles with Keynes and the market 
socialists.  What Hoover wishes to explain is Hayek's move to a more 
"ideologized" perspective. Hoover's answer is that an important explanation 
for that move is Hayek's contentious divorce from his first wife Hella and 
remarriage to his first love Helene in the early 1950s. 
 
In Ebenstein's (2001) recent biography, as well as Caldwell's recent book 
(2003), more details of Hayek's divorce and remarriage have come to public 
attention.  The archival materials do not paint a very pretty picture, with 
Hayek going through a number of legal maneuvers, including taking a 
one-term position in Arkansas to take advantage of their liberal divorce 
laws, so as to force a divorce on Hella that she would not consent to.  In 
addition, the archival materials suggest he made limited provisions for his 
kids, although there appears to be some dispute about that claim as newer 
archival materials may tell a different story.  Hoover makes much of this 
series of events, seeing them as possibly central to Hayek's "increasingly 
antistatist attitudes" because restrictive divorce laws overly limited 
individual choice (p. 232).  Hoover also adds some important details about 
Hayek's contacts with the nascent American conservative movement of the 
post-War era, and the role it played in bringing him to the U.S. and making 
the divorce possible. Hayek's personal circumstances and the relationships 
that he was cultivating with U.S. conservatives are seen by Hoover as a 
turning point in Hayek's identity formation that led to a more ideological 
approach to his understanding of the social world. 
 
In offering a few words of criticism, I will keep my focus on his treatment 
of Hayek, as that is the one of the three I am most capable of commenting 
on, and because some of the issues I wish to raise apply more generally. 
Although the approach Hoover takes has its moments of insight, I find it 
too psychologically driven in key places.  It is difficult to deny that 
psychological, personal, and relationship factors matter for the ways in 
which a thinker's ideas might evolve over time. However, the relative 
weight those factors should play as compared to genuine moments of learning 
and discovery, as well as the pressure exerted on a thinker by other 
people's ideas, is a matter of much more uncertainty.  For example, Hayek's 
move to political philosophy and his increasing "anti-statism" could be 
explained a variety of other ways. Caldwell (2003) offers one such 
explanation, seeing it as part of a broader evolution in Hayek toward 
grasping the nature of the social sciences, and hence society, in response 
to his perceived defeat at the hands of Keynes and the market socialists.  
 From Hoover's perspective, why would Hayek turn toward methodology and the 
theory of mind at the very same time he is angling for his divorce and 
becoming a "client" of conservative foundations?  The book contains no 
references to the essays that comprised _The Counter-Revolution of Science_ 
nor _The Sensory Order_, both of which were written during this stormy 
period of the late 40s and early 50s, and neither of which has an obvious 
connection to the divorce. Could it be that Hayek's turn toward political 
philosophy was the product of his engaging in the very same process of 
"learning and discovery" that Hoover attributes so charitably to Keynes's 
shifting ideas? 
 
This points to a more general problem with Hoover's treatment: he relies 
mostly on the major books of each thinker as well as archival material, and 
does very little with journal articles and other forms of publication.  In 
the case of Hayek, this leads to several problems, one of which is not 
seeing the alternative, and in my belief, more plausible explanation for 
Hayek's turn toward political philosophy.  Granted, trying to deal with 
three major thinkers in a 300-page book, one is limited, but one also has 
an obligation to provide as complete treatment as possible.  Two examples 
of this problem with respect to Hayek are his misreading of Hayek's 
critique of social justice and his assertion that Hayek provides no 
evidence for his various claims about the division and effective use of 
knowledge in the market. 
 
Hoover (p. 228) claims that Hayek argues that "if morality is an attribute 
only of individual voluntary acts, not of collective or coerced actions, 
then government actions are amoral at best."  However, that is not Hayek's 
position.  Rather he claims that morality can only be ascribed to 
_intentions_ not to patterns of outcomes that are unintended consequences. 
The dichotomy for Hayek is between the intended (to which attributions of 
morality apply) and the unintended (to which they do not because they were 
not the product of intentional choice).  Thus, Hayek's critique of social 
justice is that market outcomes, such as the distribution of income, are 
not the product of anyone's intention, thus they cannot be judged immoral 
or unjust. Governments, or other collectives such as firms and families, 
can take actions that can be judged moral or immoral, or just or unjust, 
just as individuals can.  Hoover does not cite volume two of _Law, 
Legislation, and Liberty_ (Hayek 1977), where this argument is spelled out 
most clearly. 
 
In his treatment of Hayek's work on knowledge, Hoover does not cite any of 
Hayek's seminal papers (1937, 1945, 1978), all of which provide arguments 
for his contention that markets serve as knowledge discovery and conveying 
social processes.  Hayek provides the "scientific" evidence for his view of 
knowledge in _The Sensory Order_ (1952) and in several essays in the late 
1960s.  None of that work is cited, either. Nowhere in the book does Hoover 
discuss Hayek's distinction between scientific, articulate knowledge, and 
the tacit and contextual knowledge "of time and place." This distinction is 
crucial to understanding Hayek's epistemic defense of the market and 
critique of many forms of state intervention, yet it makes no appearance 
here when those subjects are treated.  Again, no author can be expected to 
do it all, but then the author should be careful where he treads. 
 
Hoover's own ideological perspective is at work in his treatment of Hayek 
as well.  One example of this is his continued insistence that Hayek's 
defense of capitalism is a defense of economic privilege and that his 
defense of freedom of choice works to the benefit of the wealthy and to the 
detriment of the poor.  This may or may not be true, but, importantly, it 
was not Hayek's (1973: p. 62) view of the matter: 'Capitalism' is ... 
always [a] misleading [name] because it suggests a system which mainly 
benefits the capitalists, while it is in fact a system which imposes upon 
enterprise a discipline under which the managers chafe and which each 
endeavours to escape. The principle of charitable interpretation once again 
rears its head and suggests that Hoover should have been more circumspect 
in making such claims. 
 
 The second example is Hoover's word choice in describing Hayek's ideas and those of his
followers.  The last third of the book is littered with invocations of "scripture,"
"proselytize," "faith," "corps of committed believers," and even "peddlers."  This is
unfair both to Hayek and to those who attempted to put his ideas into practice.  After
all, there would appear to be no less reason to apply the same sort of language to Laskian
socialists or Keynesian technocrats.  Were not _The General Theory_ and Samuelson equally
the Old and New Testament of the macroeconomics of the post-War era?  To Hoover, the
Laskians are cute, well-meaning, but overly radical seekers of social justice and the
Keynesians are open-minded, flexible, morally-aware intellectuals out to save the Western
world from the excesses of capitalism and socialism, but Hayek and the Hayekians are the
equivalent of fundamentalists for whom the defense of the market is an article of "faith"
rather than a reasoned argument for what is best for society.
 
It is unfortunate that a book that tells, for the first two-thirds, such a 
wonderful and rich story of three key players in the development of 
economics and of twentieth-century politics ends up with not "economics as 
ideology" but "ideology as intellectual biography" when it comes to making 
sense of that story.  However, the strengths of the first eight chapters 
ultimately outweigh the problems in the last few, making this a useful read 
for historians of economics and economic thought, as well as those with an 
interest in the development of political thought in the twentieth century. 
 
References: 
 
Caldwell, Bruce.  2003.  _Hayek's Challenge: An Intellectual Biography of 
F.A. Hayek_. Chicago:  University of Chicago Press. 
 
Ebenstein, Alan. 2001.  _Friedrich Hayek: A Biography_.  New York: 
Palgrave. 
 
Hayek, F.A. 1937.  "Economics and Knowledge," reprinted in _Individualism 
and Economic Order_, Chicago:  University of Chicago Press, 1948. 
 
Hayek, F.A. 1945.  "The Use of Knowledge in Society," reprinted in 
_Individualism and Economic Order_, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 
1948. 
 
Hayek, F.A. 1952.  _The Sensory Order_, Chicago:  University of Chicago 
Press. 
 
Hayek, F.A. 1973.  _Law, Legislation, and Liberty_, volume 1, Chicago: 
University of Chicago Press. 
 
Hayek, F.A. 1977.  _Law, Legislation, and Liberty_, volume 2, Chicago: 
University of Chicago Press 
 
Hayek, F.A. 1978.  "Competition as a Discovery Procedure," in _New Studies 
in Politics, Philosophy, Economics and the History of Ideas_, Chicago: 
University of Chicago Press. 
 
 Steven Horwitz is Professor of Economics and Associate Dean of the First Year at St.
Lawrence University in Canton, NY and is the author of _Microfoundations and
Macroeconomics: An Austrian Perspective_ (Routledge 2000).
 
Copyright (c) 2004 by EH.Net. All rights reserved. This work may be copied 
for non-profit educational uses if proper credit is given to the author and 
the list. For other permission, please contact the EH.Net Administrator 
([log in to unmask]; Telephone: 513-529-2229). Published by EH.Net (April 
2004). All EH.Net reviews are archived at http://www.eh.net/BookReview.    
 
------------ FOOTER TO HES POSTING ------------ 
For information, send the message "info HES" to [log in to unmask] 
 

ATOM RSS1 RSS2