------------ EH.NET BOOK REVIEW --------------
Published by EH.NET (September 2004)
Leonidas Montes, _Adam Smith in Context: A Critical Reassessment of
Some Central Components of His Thought_. New York: Palgrave
Macmillan, 2004. xii + 186 pp. $69.95 (hardcover), ISBN:
1-4039-1256-4.
Reviewed by Peter McNamara, Department of Political Science, Utah
State University.
Leonidas Montes's _Adam Smith in Context_ has two virtues: first, it
provides a useful, concise account of the unwieldy and rapidly
increasing literature on Adam Smith and, second, it presents the
author's own views on Smith which, while not entirely original,
constitute a thoughtful fine-tuning of the so-called civic humanist
approach to Smith. The book is in two unequal parts. The first and
larger part discusses Smith's moral theory. The second part of the
book is an analysis of Newton's influence on Smith's economic
methodology. Montes follows Quentin Skinner's interpretative approach
which emphasizes reading texts in their historical context. According
to Montes, the classical influence on Smith has been a neglected
context. This dimension of his book makes a nice contrast with Gloria
Vivenza's recently translated _Adam Smith and the Classics_ (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2002) with which Montes has many
disagreements, some small, some large.
Montes begins with the Adam Smith Problem: the suggestion that there
is a conflict between Smith's moral theory based on sympathy and his
economic theory based on self-interest. While many influential Smith
scholars have viewed it as a "pseudo-problem," Montes (fortunately)
takes it seriously. He provides a very welcome account of the
emergence of the problem in Germany in the nineteenth century that
shows the connection between the beginnings of the German Historical
School of economics and the identification of the Adam Smith Problem.
Both, it turns out, grew out of a reaction against British policies
and British ideas, particularly the free trade doctrines that Smith
did so much to establish. Smith and Britain were caricatured as
single-minded advocates of self-interest. On this basis, Smith's
moral theory seemed anomalous. Montes believes that the usual way of
dispatching the Problem -- by distinguishing "sympathy" from
"benevolence" and pointing out that sympathy is the mechanism by
which moral judgment takes place and thus not in conflict with
self-interest -- is too quick and, somewhat paradoxically, concedes
too much to the terms of debate established by the original
proponents of the Adam Smith Problem.
To make his point, Montes reviews three critical elements of Smith's
moral theory. First, Montes argues that sympathy is not simply a
means for making moral judgments. It is also a _motive_ for moral
conduct because the very act of sympathizing involves an imaginative
leap on our part into someone else's situation. It is as much a
disposition to act as it is a means of rendering moral judgment. As a
motive, it reflects our fundamentally social nature. The second
element of Smith's moral theory that Montes dwells on is
self-command. Montes draws attention to the pivotal role self-command
plays in Smith's overall account of the virtues. It is not only one
of the Smithian cardinal virtues, it is also a prerequisite for the
performance of the other virtues. Montes begins with a discussion of
the general background to Smith's account of the virtues. He argues
that Smith should be seen in light of the classical tradition in
which there was a close link between virtue and manliness. According
to Montes, this connection lives on in Smith's language, in his moral
theory, and in his policy prescriptions. With regard to this last
area, Montes revisits the militia versus standing army debate and
tries to show that while Smith favored a standing army he saw the
moral merit of a militia's contribution to citizen virtue. The
discussion of self-command is closely tied to the third of Montes's
main points about Smith's moral theory: Smith's account of propriety
makes him proto-Kantian rather than utilitarian or proto-utilitarian.
Propriety is a judgment of moral good made with reference to the
intention behind an action and without reference to the consequences.
A key example cited by Montes is Smith's claim that we approve of the
heroic valor -- the self-command -- of a soldier even if his cause is
unjust; that is, regardless of consequences of the action. These
accounts of sympathy, self-command, and propriety lead Montes to
argue repeatedly against the idea that Smith's thought bears any
simple relation to the crude Robinson Crusoe individualism of later
economists.
This observation prepares us somewhat for the abrupt shift in the
last part of the book to questions of economic methodology.
Specifically, Montes asks: was Smith a Newtonian? Montes believes he
was but not for reasons scholars usually give. According to Montes,
Smith was not a proponent of a mathematical-deductive method and he
was certainly not a proponent of an embryonic form of Walrasian
general equilibrium theory. The passages usually cited to support
this view are in Montes's opinion largely metaphorical. Smith was,
however, a Newtonian in the deeper sense that like Newton he wished
to uncover the pieces of the connecting chain that links together
events -- "the real structures underlying phenomena" (p. 149). In
this Montes sees a connection between Smith and his own preference
for "critical realism" as an approach in economics.
One might find many areas of disagreement with Montes's reading of
Smith both from within the interpretative approach he uses and from
without. Let me just raise one question with regard to Smith's moral
theory. One feature of it which Montes does not explore is the
potential hazard that lurks in Smith's analysis of sympathy,
self-command, and propriety. Take the example of the admiration we
feel for someone who is a hero in a bad cause. Is there not something
perverse about this? Was not Smith aware of this problem? Consider
also Smith's belief that we sympathize with the rich and the great,
regardless of their moral character, and for this reason defer to
them. Both examples point to the way in which sympathy is, perhaps, a
motive but not a _moral_ motive. I wish Montes had dealt more
explicitly with such issues. But, at the least, his useful book
helped me to think about them and a host of others one finds in the
complex thought of Adam Smith.
Peter McNamara is author of _Political Economy and Statesmanship:
Smith, Hamilton and the Foundation of the Commercial Republic_
(Northern Illinois University Press, 1997) and editor of _The Noblest
Minds: Fame, Honor, and the American Founding_ (Rowman & Littlefield,
1999).
Copyright (c) 2004 by EH.Net. All rights reserved. This work may be
copied for non-profit educational uses if proper credit is given to
the author and the list. For other permission, please contact the
EH.Net Administrator ([log in to unmask]; Telephone: 513-529-2229).
Published by EH.Net (September 2004). All EH.Net reviews are archived
at http://www.eh.net/BookReview.
-------------- FOOTER TO EH.NET BOOK REVIEW --------------
EH.Net-Review mailing list
[log in to unmask]
http://eh.net/mailman/listinfo/eh.net-review
|