SHOE Archives

Societies for the History of Economics

SHOE@YORKU.CA

Options: Use Forum View

Use Monospaced Font
Show Text Part by Default
Show All Mail Headers

Message: [<< First] [< Prev] [Next >] [Last >>]
Topic: [<< First] [< Prev] [Next >] [Last >>]
Author: [<< First] [< Prev] [Next >] [Last >>]

Print Reply
Subject:
From:
[log in to unmask] (Mohammad Gani)
Date:
Fri Mar 31 17:18:48 2006
Content-Type:
text/plain
Parts/Attachments:
text/plain (102 lines)
  
   And if Gerard thinks so, who am I, as a lowly "hagiographer", to dispute one  
   of the foremost theoreticians of modern economics. - Warren Young  
  
   I beg your pardon to point out that the above sentiment shows the highly  
   admirable qualities of loyalty and respect to seniors, but also constitutes  
   the fallacy of authority.  Being one of the foremost theoreticians gives no  
   guarantee that one is able to deliver the error-free truth.  
  
   In my reading of Debreu's 1991 paper (the AEA presidential address) [1] I see  
   a remarkable confession that also should be seen in association with Arrow's  
   impossibility theorem [2] published forty years earlier. The confession is  
   that the most ambitious enterprise of neoclassical economics to build a  
   general  equilibrium  model failed. In Arrows eyes, there is no way to  
   incorporate social choice in it. The essentially same theme is presented in  
   Debreu's paper that the construction of a grand unified theory of the economy  
   is out of reach. Unifying economics is pretty simple [3], and Debreu is  
   mistaken to say that it is out of reach. Likewise, his partner Arrow is  
   mistaken to suppose that social choice is impossible. It is extremely easy  
   to show that social choice is possible. [4]  
  
   Arrow and Debreu together of course have done the most advanced theoretical  
   work in economics, and have both been rightfully honored.  The aim of the  
   general equilibrium model is to describe the entire economy and capture all  
   its essential elements in a compact unified model.  The failure of Arrow and  
   Debreu to deliver such a model perpetuates the old problem created by Walras  
   and made unworkable by Pareto.  
  
   Walras  thought  that he described the entire economy with his general  
   equilibrium model, but he actually presented the model of economic behavior  
   of a single isolated person who produces n different goods. If there is a  
   single isolated individual who produces and consumes n different kinds of  
   goods, he must equate the production (supply) and consumption (demand) for  
   each good. If one adds matters of risk and uncertainty and considers several  
   periods,  the essential nature of the model is still that it is one of  
   autarky by a single individual.  It does not describe the economy consisting  
   of more than one person engaged in trade.  
  
   To model trade, one must necessarily connect two real goods that directly or  
   indirectly  pay  for  each other in a transaction. A basic equilibrium  
   condition in exchange is that in each individual transaction of one good  
   against another, the values must be equal so that one pays for the other.  
   Walras does not impose this condition and hence his model cannot be one of  
   exchange at all.  On must also add a budget balance in real values for each  
   person, and further set up the equality of lending and borrowing in each  
   period. All told, four equalities are requires to describe an entire economy  
   with exchange, but Walras mentions only one.  
  
   Pareto  actually  abolishes  the possibility of exchange altogether by  
   requiring  that  marginal rates of substitution in both production and  
   consumption be the same for two different people, as both must equate the  
   substitution rates to the ratio of prices. This is fundamentally mistaken.  
   The very existence of gainful trade requires that the substitution rates  
   between any two goods must differ between buyers and sellers to allow for  
   gainful trade, either in production (reflecting differences in costs) or in  
   consumption  (reflecting  differences in marginal benefits or relative  
   utilities)  or  both.  For the same reason, the idea of representative  
   individual is void ab intio: there is just no way for a seller to represent  
   a buyer, and no exchange can be described without showing both the buyer and  
   the seller with their preferences technologies and endowments. If people are  
   all alike, they cannot possibly trade and they cannot possibly have a market  
   at all.  
  
   Arrow and Debreu could not detect the basic flaw in Walras and Pareto.  
   Arrows formulation of social choice fails to set up the problem correctly  
   owing to this oversight. No society ever faces a problem of many different  
   people choosing one common good. In politics, when different voting blocks  
   prefer different candidates, the solution is a parliament with different  
   members, not the election of one member for all. If the national candidates  
   fail to command the majority, the solution for them is to articulate the  
   majority aspiration and retry the vote, and not to give up the election as  
   an impossible feat.  
  
   But in economics, there is never a need for all consumers or producers to  
   make a single choice.  Arrow did not think about allocation. If he did, he  
   would specify the budget of each party and see that social choice is very  
   simple: all different people buy all different goods according to budget and  
   preferences. If he could set up an exchange problem, he would see that  
   exchange  can  occur if and only if over any given pair of goods to be  
   exchanged against each other, the preference orders must necessarily be  
   opposite. Thus if one is to sell x and buy y, one must prefer y to x; but  
   then the buyer of x must prefer x to y. Arrows impossibility theorem implies  
   that exchange is impossible, which clearly is not true. In short, Arrow  
   enlarges the mistake of Pareto. The Arrow-Debreu model is a failure.  
   We must have the courage to raise questions, and to propose solutions.  Of  
   course other economists are to be persuaded by the force of argument and the  
   factual evidence. We cannot give up merely because there are famous people  
   who made mistakes.  
  
   Mohammad Gani  
  
   [1]. Gerard Debreu (1991): The mathematization of economic theory. American  
   Economic Review, Volume 81, No 1.  
   [2]. Kenneth Arrow (1951): Social Choice and Individual Values. New York:  
   Wiley & Sons  
   [3]. Mohammad Gani (2003): Foundations of Economic Science, Scarborough,  
   Ontario: Scholars.  
   [4] Mohammad Gani (2004): "Though Arrow Says Its Impossible, It Happens  
   Everyday," downloadable at http://ideas.repec.org/p/wpa/wuwpmi/0405008.html  
  
 

ATOM RSS1 RSS2