SHOE Archives

Societies for the History of Economics

SHOE@YORKU.CA

Options: Use Forum View

Use Monospaced Font
Show Text Part by Default
Show All Mail Headers

Message: [<< First] [< Prev] [Next >] [Last >>]
Topic: [<< First] [< Prev] [Next >] [Last >>]
Author: [<< First] [< Prev] [Next >] [Last >>]

Print Reply
Subject:
From:
[log in to unmask] (Ross B. Emmett)
Date:
Fri Mar 31 17:19:06 2006
Content-Type:
text/plain
Parts/Attachments:
text/plain (229 lines)
====================== HES POSTING =================== 
 
EH.NET BOOK REVIEW 
 
Published by EH.NET (May 1998) 
 
Peter McNamara, _Political Economy and Statesmanship: Smith, Hamilton, and 
the Foundation of the Commercial Republic_.  DeKalb: Northern Illinois 
University Press, 1998.  xi + 191 pp. $35.00 (cloth) ISBN 0-87580-228-1. 
 
Reviewed for EH.NET  by Richard Sylla, Department of Economics, Stern 
School of Business, New York University. <[log in to unmask]> 
 
 
                    TWO FOUNDING FATHERS 
 
Peter McNamara, a political scientist at Utah State University, compares 
and contrasts the political economies of Adam Smith (1723-1790), founding 
father of Economics, and Alexander Hamilton (1757-1804), the founding 
father of the United States most involved in shaping the country's 
financial and economic systems.  From a thorough study of the writings of 
the two-- and in Hamilton's case, from his activities in the public arena-- 
McNamara draws out a number of implications and conclusions.  His bottom 
line may surprise you, although it did not surprise me:  "The chief 
conclusion...is that the _example_ of Hamilton's words and deeds provides a 
more useful guide for a liberal statesman than does the economic _model_ 
yielded by Smith's science of political economy" (McNamara's emphasis). 
This conclusion is related to McNamara's own agenda, to which I shall 
return. 
 
The careers of Smith and Hamilton intersected in the great events of the 
last quarter of the 18th century.  _The Wealth of Nations_ appeared just 
before the Declaration of Independence, and in it Smith devoted some 
attention to the "colonial disturbances."  He gave little credence to 
American protests over taxes and mercantilist regulations.  Taxation of the 
colonies was justified by Britain's costs of defending them, and 
regulation-- while bad in principle-- had done little actual harm.  For 
Smith, the Americans' real economic advantage was, and long would remain, 
agriculture.  Smith thought the Americans were fortunate in this, because 
his theories had persuaded him that the productivity of agriculture was 
superior to that of either manufacturing or commerce.  He also thought that 
rural life was less degrading of the human spirit than life in cities. 
 
Smith's preferred solution to the colonial disturbances was peaceful 
separation.  By saving on the costs of defense, this was in Britain's 
interest.  But he realized that peaceful separation was "visionary" because 
it conflicted with the "pride" of the British nation and its ruling 
classes.  His fallback position was therefore to grant the colonies free 
trade and representation in Parliament.  That would likely satisfy the 
ambitions of colonial politicians.  Given the superior productivity of 
agriculture and therefore America's economic and demographic prospects, 
America's leading men could look forward to the day when the seat of empire 
would move there.  Had George III and Lord North followed Smith's advice, 
Parliament might now meet in Chicago, Toronto, or Kansas City, with Tony 
Blair, Jean Chretien, or Bill Clinton as Prime Minister, and the British 
Isles as somewhat more populated constituencies than Hawaii, Bermuda, 
Puerto Rico, and the Falklands. 
 
Smith's work was well known to the U.S. founding fathers.  His political 
economy extolling reason, enlightened self-interest, free trade, 
agriculture and rural life, and America's long-term prospects appealed to 
the likes of Jefferson, the idealist, and Madison, the realist, both 
members of Virginia's planter aristocracy.  Much of it also appealed to 
Hamilton, like Madison a realist, but one with a more commercial and 
industrial outlook.  But parts of Smith did not.  Hamilton's 1791 Report on 
Manufactures, as has often been noted, is an extended and critical 
commentary on Smith's views.  These views, given their appeal to many U.S. 
leaders, had to be addressed and in some cases refuted if Hamilton was to 
achieve his goals. 
 
Because he dared to disagree with Smith and because of Smith's icon-like 
status amongst Jeffersonians, libertarians, and mainstream and 
public-choice economists, Hamilton's detractors have tended to dismiss him 
as a mercantilist, a regulator, and a statist.  His admirers, in contrast, 
have viewed him as a modernizer, an advocate of economic growth and 
development with advanced insights into the roles technology and finance 
would play in them.  Hamilton was not encumbered with the baggage of 
Smith's labor theory of value, his quaint theoretical notions of 
agriculture's superior productivity, his inadequate appreciation of new 
industrial technologies, his primitive ideas on money and finance, his 
laissez-faire ideology regarding government, or his undeveloped concepts of 
the threats nation-states might pose to one another in pursuing their real 
or imagined self-interests. 
 
McNamara's contribution, it seems to me, is to move to the side these 
common characterizations and caricatures of Smith and Hamilton, and to 
raise to a higher plane the analysis of their agreements and differences. 
Simply put, McNamara says that the key difference between Smith and 
Hamilton is over method.  Smith developed political economy as a deductive 
system, the conclusions of which should be the main guides to economic 
policy.  Hamilton, on the other hand, distrusted the conclusions of 
deductive systems as practical guides to policy, preferring instead to rely 
on experience and history. 
 
Smith launched a tradition that would revolutionize political economy.  He 
began with broad, seemingly self-evident assumptions, such as that every 
person had a natural and rational interest in bettering his or her 
condition.  He then deduced from the assumptions conclusions as to the 
optimality of free trade and the folly of governmental interferences with 
it.  While still a revolutionary soldier and apparently before reading 
Smith, Hamilton in 1779 pronounced his judgment on deriving policy from 
such grand deductive systems: "A great source of error in disquisitions of 
this nature," Hamilton wrote in a long letter, "is the judging of events by 
abstract calculations, which though 'geometrically true' are 'practically 
false' as they relate to the concerns of beings governed more by passion 
and prejudice than by an enlightened sense of their interests." 
 
McNamara shows that a recurring theme of Hamilton's thought, and of his 
statecraft, was the notion that passions and prejudices were at least as 
powerful in human affairs as rational self-interest.  In his view, trade in 
history expanded not so much because the traders pursued their 
self-interest-- other traders had just as much of an interest in stopping 
them-- but because the enlightened statesmen of the Dutch Republic, 
England, and France established policies that overcame parochial passions 
and prejudices.  Two centuries later, I would note, the economic historian 
Eli Heckscher said much the same thing in his great study, _Mercantilism_. 
 
The problem as Hamilton saw it was that not all statesmen were enlightened. 
The pride of British leaders overcame their and their country's interest 
when they rejected Adam Smith's suggestions for preventing the American 
Revolution. As a result of British pride and prejudice, Hamilton had to 
spend six years of his life fighting the redcoats and the Hessians.  In 
war, he learned to distrust the practicality of deductions based on 
assumptions of rational self-interest.  When the war was over, Hamilton saw 
American proponents of state sovereignty and weak confederation, again for 
reasons of passion and prejudice, condemning the country for which he had 
fought to an early breakup and the endless commercial and political warfare 
that plagued the states of Europe. 
 
Hamilton's solution, formulated in the 1780s with Madison and other 
nationalists, was a strong federal government to defend the United States 
against external threats and to subject the states to a higher sovereignty 
that would avoid European-like strife in North America.  The federal 
government would have to have strong finances-- public credit, a national 
bank, a common currency.  Establishing these would also promote a financial 
system for the country that would give rise to "a general spirit of 
improvement," or economic development.  The passions and prejudices of 
foreign nations also suggested to Hamilton that the U.S. government would 
be wise to take measures promoting manufactures, to diversify the American 
economy, put idle resources to work, and capture advantages of new 
technologies.  This in essence is McNamara's interpretation of Hamilton's 
tenure as the new nation's Secretary of the Treasury from 1789 to 1795. 
 
To keep the federal government itself from becoming a threat to liberty, 
Hamilton worked with other nationalists to create the Constitution's 
elaborate system of checks and balances.  A strong executive (president) 
and an independent judiciary would counterbalance the legislative supremacy 
favored by many Americans.  In Hamilton's conception, McNamara argues, 
constitutional government, not Smith's deductive science of political 
economy, set the parameters for economic statesmanship. 
 
McNamara's skillful and thorough development of Smith's and Hamilton's 
contrasting approaches to political economy is the main contribution of his 
book.  Each approach proved influential in U.S. history. Comparing and 
contrasting the Scottish theorist and system builder with the American 
applied economist and statesman helps us to understand the achievements and 
continuing appeal of each man's thought, and also Hamilton's deeds.  In 
practice, America's political economy has been mainly Hamiltonian, and with 
Hamiltonian results-- a nation that is more powerful, better governed, and 
richer than just about any other.  Yet its dominant theory of political 
economy is still pretty much Adam Smith. 
 
McNamara's study is provocative.  He makes a strong case-- which no doubt 
will be contested-- for Hamilton as the more insightful and relevant 
thinker on political economy.  But I think he may go too far in suggesting 
that Hamiltonian precepts of constitutional government could-- and maybe 
should-- replace the insights of Smith and mainstream economics in guiding 
statesmen.  Smith, like Hamilton, recognized that there were exceptions to 
the general presumption for free trade.  And Hamilton understood-- even 
developed-- insights of deductive economic theory.  In the Report on 
Manufactures, for example, he held that subsidies were better than tariffs 
as a method of promoting desired activities because they achieved the 
intended results without making the consumer pay a higher price. 
Economics, wise economists instruct us, is a bag of tools, and there is 
room under the big tent of political economy for Smithian and Hamiltonian 
insights. 
 
McNamara doesn't like mainstream, deductive economics.  His agenda calls or 
getting away from it, at least in political economy, and emphasizing 
instead the concept of statesmanship.  I doubt he will persuade economists, 
though. If they can't fit entrepreneurship into their models, and therefore 
ignore it, how likely are they to find a place for statesmanship? 
Political scientists and historians will have to carry that torch. 
 
I  also wonder if McNamara is right in suggesting that Hamilton's example 
of economic statesmanship has much to offer new and developing nations, 
although I agree with him that it is relevant to current U.S. political 
economy, and also relevant in studying U.S. economic history.  The lesson 
from Hamilton would seem to be to ground political economy in 
constitutional government and the rule of law.  But using that as policy 
advice to leaders of new and developing nations strikes me as about as 
promising as telling aspiring musicians to study and follow Mozart's 
example if they want to become great composers. 
 
I have spent a lot of time studying Hamilton.  He was, I think, altogether 
exceptional in his ability to define a problem, think it through, come up 
with a good solution, persuade others that it was the right thing to do, 
and then see to it that the solution was implemented.  As the British 
writer Paul Johnson says in his recent _A History of the American People_, 
"The truth is, Hamilton was a genius-- the only one of the Founding Fathers 
fully entitled to that accolade-- and he had the elusive, indefinable 
characteristics of genius." Europeans-- Talleyrand and Lord Bryce are 
additional examples-- have recognized that genius for two centuries. 
Without a Hamilton, they are still trying to implement Hamiltonian 
political economy.  So when McNamara recommends following Hamilton's 
example as a guide to political economy elsewhere, he comes perilously 
close to adopting the sort of mainstream, "can-opener" economics he so 
dislikes:  Assume we have a genius. 
 
Richard Sylla 
Department of Economics 
Stern School of Business 
New York University 
 
The Federal Reserve Bank of St. Louis REVIEW (May/June 1998) is scheduled 
to publish Sylla's paper, "U.S. Securities Markets and the Banking System, 
1790-1840," along with a comment on it by Kenneth Snowden.  Sylla's latest 
research is on the early U.S. financial system, particularly the 
development of securities markets. 
 
Copyright (c) 1998 by EH.NET and H-Net.  All rights reserved.  This work 
may be copied for non-profit educational uses if proper credit is given to 
the author and the list.  For other permission, please contact the EH.NET 
Administrator.  ([log in to unmask], Telephone: 513-529-2850; Fax: 
513-529-6992) 
 
============ FOOTER TO HES POSTING ============ 
For information, send the message "info HES" to [log in to unmask] 

ATOM RSS1 RSS2