SHOE Archives

Societies for the History of Economics

SHOE@YORKU.CA

Options: Use Forum View

Use Monospaced Font
Show Text Part by Default
Show All Mail Headers

Message: [<< First] [< Prev] [Next >] [Last >>]
Topic: [<< First] [< Prev] [Next >] [Last >>]
Author: [<< First] [< Prev] [Next >] [Last >>]

Print Reply
Subject:
From:
[log in to unmask] (Mohammad Gani)
Date:
Fri Mar 31 17:18:50 2006
Content-Type:
text/plain
Parts/Attachments:
text/plain (161 lines)
  
   Thanks  to  Richard  Lipsey.  I read the second edition of his book in  
   undergraduate days and I am grateful for awakening a suspicion that there  
   was something behind the eternal confusion with the reversal of axis. I have  
   wrestled with this confusion for thirty plus years.  
    1. Marshall did not merely reverse the axis. It is a simple matter of  
       convention whether one puts the independent variable on one or the other  
       axis, and as such should not confuse anyone. Behind this axis reversal,  
       Marshall seemingly killed economic science by aborting causation in two  
       fundamental  ways:  by  sabotaging  epistemology and by perverting  
       methodology.  
    2. In epistemology, the goal of science is to discover and articulate the  
       causation, and Marshall did not pursue the study of causation. How could  
       anybody ever even define demand without taking price as predetermined,  
       far less let demand determine price? Can there be demand if the buyer  
       has no idea what the price is? To suppose that demand determines price  
       is a sabotage of epistemology. Price can never be set by one party: it  
       must without exception be set by agreement between the buyer and the  
       seller.  One cannot represent the buyer with a demand curve and a seller  
       with a supply curve at all: one must show the buyer with income and  
       preference, and the seller with technology and endowments. Equality of  
       demand and supply determines only the quantity, and cannot possibly  
       determine the price. The price of x is the quantity of y that pays for x  
       (per unit), and the equality of demand for and supply of x surely can in  
       no way determine the quantity of y that pays for x. In short, the change  
       in price is causally based on income from the buyers side and cost from  
       the  sellers  side,  and Marshall avoids both. Marshall presents a  
       self-contradiction: price determines demand and supply, and then demand  
       and supply determine price. His pupil Keynes was brighter, and got the  
       idea that (aggregate) demand and (aggregate) supply determine output not  
       price, and yet nobody noticed the reversal of Marshall by his pupil.  
    3. In methodology, Marshall violated the very old idea enshrined by the  
       Buddha in the parable of six blind men trying to study an elephant.  
       Partial equilibrium is bound to distort causality because it permits one  
       to contradict the omitted but causally linked parts. The buyer must be a  
       seller of something to earn the income with which he proposes to buy  
       something, and that must not be left out as an exogenous variable,  
       because that is very much an endogenous one. One can learn about neither  
       price nor quantity unless one brings the production and consumption by  
       each individual together in one full model: a partial model will never  
       do. Thus Marshall is surely mistaken to suppose that an increase in  
       demand can lead to an increase in price. It cannot. An increase in  
       income can allow an increase in demand at a given price, or an increase  
       in price for a given quantity, or a combination of both. If income is  
       fixed, an increase is demand is possible only with a decrease in price.  
       In consumer equilibrium, the price must be equal to lambda times the  
       marginal utility of the good and the lambda is based on income. Without  
       a change in income, no change in price is possible unless Marshall  
       violates the equilibrium condition just mentioned: price must be equal  
       to lambda times marginal utility. Just as the blind man who said the  
       elephant was a curved and bony stick (after partially touching the tusk  
       and ignoring the rest of the elephant), the partial model is necessarily  
       distorted.  
  
  
   Walras did it right with a general equilibrium model. The key culprit behind  
   the Marshallian confusion is the very method of isolating the issue of  
   determining variables, for leaving the casual variables out. An increase in  
   demand cannot increase price: an increase in income can.  
  
                Marshalls  diagram  of demand and supply of one good is a  
   methodological absurdity: it is impossible for a single good to be bought  
   and sold, because there must be at least two goods to pay for each other.  
   Thus  the  demand  for x must be made with an offer of supply of y and  
   vice-versa in barter. Marshall got it wrong, and Walras got it right.  
  
               With one good, there can be at most a numeraire to convert the  
   quantity into value. The numeraire factor is not price. A single goods  
   demand-supply intersection can at most determine its numeraire unit, not its  
   price. The price must be a ratio. The so-called nominal price is a mistaken  
   term to denote the numeraire value: it should not be called price.  
  
  
   2.  Walras did it right to set up a general equilibrium model in which  
   quantities are the dependent variables under predetermined or independent  
   prices. Walras does not have a theory of price. He shows how the quantities  
   are determined by equating the production and consumption for each good.  
   His  aim  is to show that a unique set of prices would ensure that all  
   quantities reached equilibrium, but he did not show how those prices would  
   be reached. He left the work for us, and we failed mightily. The auction  
   idea is meaningless in causal sense: the job is to describe the auction  
   process.  
  
  
   3.  Walras  provides a valid starting point for a theory of price, but  
   Marshall does not. To make any progress towards developing a theory of  
   price,  the  first  need  is  to  throw  away  Marshall's  mistake and  
   self-contradiction. Here are the steps. First, take an autarkic individual  
   who produces n different goods. There is no market and hence no market  
   price. But optimization means that the subsistence producer must equalize  
   the production of each good with its consumption, and that the marginal rate  
   of  substitution  in  production must be equal to the marginal rate of  
   substitution  in consumption for any pair of goods. The common rate of  
   substitution in both production and consumption provides the equilibrium  
   rate of substitution under autarky, and may be regarded as shadow price  
   ratios. These are not market price ratios.  
  
   3. To get at market price (as a ratio), one must introduce entrepreneurship  
   for profit. An optimizer does not seek profit, but merely allocates what he  
   already has. An entrepreneur seeks profit and creates new value that did not  
   exist before. He can do this by exchange such that the buyer offers a price  
   higher than the marginal cost of the producer but lower than the marginal  
   opportunity cost of the same good if the buyer were to produce the good. To  
   formalize this, one must add another set of equations to the Walrasian  
   model. Those equations must show that in each transaction, the value of the  
   first good which is paid for by the second good is equal to the value of the  
   second good. The price of the first good in the market then is the quantity  
   of the second good per unit of the first good. For the seller of the first  
   good, the quantity of the second good received in payment must be higher  
   than the quantity of the second good he could produce in substitution of the  
   first; for the buyer of the first good, the quantity of the second good he  
   pays out must be lower than the quantity of the second good he could produce  
   in substitution if he produced the second good instead of the first. The  
   price then must be settled by bargaining between the buyer and the seller.  
   It must be higher than the sellers production cost and lower than the buyers  
   production cost, both measured in terms of the other good. The same argument  
   can be repeated with marginal utility in place of marginal cost.  
  
  
    4. To put it in gist, the optimizer is a price taker who chooses only the  
       quantities and not the price, while the entrepreneur is someone who does  
       not choose quantities, but prices. It is as if producers presume some  
       expected price, say from their sense of immediate past, and choose  
       quantities  optimally.  Then  they  go  to  the  market and become  
       entrepreneurs. They already have the quantities, and now they must  
       choose prices to set their values such that the goods that pay for each  
       other become equal in value, namely, such that a certain quantity of the  
       second good pays fully and fairly for a unit of the first good. Walras  
       can be and must be retained, but Marshall, NAUGHT. Price theory must  
       presume that the quantities have already been chosen and have arrived in  
       the market. A dynamic model will of course show what happens in the next  
       round of quantity choices after the change in price by todays market  
       clearing.  
    5. The foundation of price theory is the idea of equivalence, namely that  
       the two goods that pay for each other must have equal value. Price is  
       the ratio to establish this equivalence. One must go beyond Walras to  
       show the equivalence. One can see the essential validity of classical  
       price theory if one thinks of value as the weight of demand and supply.  
       Thus suppose that at the price of previous day, the value of todays  
       demand is larger than the value of supply. We can visualize a scale in  
       which one side takes the demand and the other side takes the supply and  
       the scale must come to a balance. Now, if the previous days price makes  
       demand heavier than supply, the rise in price will increase the weight  
       (value) of supply (and with some reduction in quantity from the demand  
       side) will reduce the weight of demand until balance is established.  In  
       the abstract, this mechanical process seems to tell the story right.  
       However, we must tell the human story of the buyers and sellers as  
       entrepreneurs.  This means that instead of a machine automatically  
       balancing demands with supplies in terms of value by adjusting prices,  
       we must show the human process of bargaining. Of course one kind of  
       bargain may appear like auction, but an auction as such does not fully  
       reflect the price-setting process. We must have the arbitrageur here.  
  
  
   How come we have too much of Marshall and too little of Walras?  
  
  
   Mohammad Gani  
  
 

ATOM RSS1 RSS2