------------ EH.NET BOOK REVIEW --------------
Published by EH.NET (March 2008)
Geoffrey M. Hodgson, _Economics in the Shadows of Darwin and Marx:
Essays on Institutional and Evolutionary Themes_. Cheltenham, UK:
Edward Elgar, 2006. viii + 265 pp. $100 (cloth), ISBN: 1-84542-497-2.
Reviewed for EH.NET by Gary Mongiovi, Department of Economics and
Finance, St John's University.
Charles Darwin and Karl Marx, each in his own way, radically
transformed our understanding of human history. Marx developed a
powerful theory of how economic systems change over time. But
Darwin's theory of natural selection has become the preferred
metaphor of social scientists who want to understand how institutions
emerge, take root and evolve. One recent example of this
"evolutionary turn" is the hypothesis put forth by Gregory Clark in
_A Farewell to Alms_ (Princeton University Press, 2007), that
England's industrialization in the early nineteenth century can be
explained by the high fertility of the medieval nobility, who,
through a process of natural or cultural selection, infused the
country's population with traits conducive to economic growth. In
another recent book, Niall Ferguson draws upon Darwinian principles
to account for, and justify, the modern financial system (see _The
Evolution of Financial Services _, Oliver Wyman, 2007). In the book
under review, Geoffrey M. Hodgson, Research Professor in Business
Studies at the University of Hertfordshire, argues in the same vein
that Darwin rather than Marx provides the appropriate model for
making sense of socio-economic change.
Marx read _On the Origin of Species_ in late 1860. His initial
reaction was positive; he wrote to Ferdinand Lassalle in January 1861
that "Darwin's work is most important and suits my purpose in that it
provides a basis in natural science for the historical class
struggle" (K. Marx and F. Engels, _Collected Works_, Vol. 41, p. 246;
International Publishers, 1985). But Marx's enthusiasm began to wane
as soon as it dawned on him how much Darwin owed to Malthus. In June
1862 Marx commented to Engels that "Darwin rediscovers among the
beasts and plants, the society of England with its divisions of
labour, competition, opening up of new markets, 'inventions,' and
Malthusian 'struggle for existence.' It is Hobbes' bellum omnium
contra omnes ..." (_Collected Works_, Vol. 41, p. 381). Marx
anticipated that reactionaries would appeal to Darwin's theory as "a
conclusive reason for human society never to emancipate itself from
its bestiality" (_Collected Works_, Vol. 43, p. 217). By 1866, Marx
was championing Pierre Tr?maux's _Origine et Transformations de
l'Homme et des autres ?tres_ (Paris, 1865) -- now justly forgotten --
as a "significant advance over Darwin." For Marx, Tr?maux's great
improvement was that he placed progress at the center of his
conception of evolution, whereas "Darwin regards [progress] as purely
accidental ..." (_Collected Works_, Vol. 42, p. 304).
Marx's endorsement of Tr?maux over Darwin was a serious lapse in
judgment. But the misstep is explained by the affinities between
Tr?maux's theory and Marx's project to expose a set of forces that
drive socio-economic development. Opposition to this idea that
history has a "logic" is at the heart of Hodgson's coolness toward
Marx. Whereas Darwin recognized that biological systems are open --
subject to external forces like climate change or species migration
-- Marx, Hodgson charges, explains capitalism's historical trajectory
almost entirely in terms of internal mechanisms. Hodgson further
contends that Marx ascribes to these mechanisms a teleological
character that is incompatible with the open-endedness of Darwinian
evolution: they propel the system toward collapse, and set the stage
for the next phase of human history, socialism. In biological
systems, new traits originate as random mutations, and proliferate if
they confer some survival advantage on an organism or population in
the prevailing environmental conditions; these new traits may in turn
react back on the natural environment. Because the biological system
is open, and its constituent elements interact with one another in
complex ways, the outcome of the process is not susceptible of
prediction: there is no determinate end-point. In this respect,
Darwin's perspective is closer than Marx's to the "old
institutionalist" tradition that has inspired Hodgson's work over the
past two decades.
Hodgson wrongly asserts that Marxism overlooks the indispensable
social functions of customs and institutions as repositories of
collective knowledge. Marx knew that institutions evolve as solutions
to problems that individuals and groups encounter in going about
their business; in his account of how capitalism develops, custom is
a crucial element of the superstructure that reinforces the
underlying economic basis of society. Marx saw also that institutions
exhibit inertia: they persist long after the circumstances that gave
rise to them have disappeared. As often as not, the new institutions
themselves helped to bring about the transformation of the material
conditions of society. This disjunction between institutions and the
evolving mode of production, Marx hypothesized, generates tensions,
or contradictions, that lead eventually to the withering of old
institutions and their replacement by new ones: a socio-economic
system is pushed forward through history by the tensions generated by
the production relations which form the system's institutional core.
Hodgson does not consider whether this bold hypothesis is a fruitful
way to approach the analysis of socio-economic change; he simply
dismisses it as "teleological" and moves on.
Social Darwinists like Herbert Spencer, William Graham Sumner and, in
our own day, Charles Murray maintain that natural selection accounts
for the misery that market economies inflict on large numbers of
people: the poor are poor because they are inferior or unfit in some
objective sense. This is not an application of a metaphor, but a
claim about actual social and biological processes. Though its
environmental niche is small, Social Darwinism, now generally
regarded as morally repugnant and empirically vacuous, poses
something of a difficulty for anyone who wants to argue that the
theory of evolution provides an apt template for the explanation of
social processes. In Chapter 3 Hodgson rescues Darwinism from this
ditch. He points out that the term "Social Darwinism" was rarely used
before the mid-1920s, and when it was used it was usually deployed by
progressives against free-market fundamentalists. We learn also that
the writers conventionally labeled Social Darwinists were in fact not
genuine Darwinians. But the misapplication of allegedly Darwinian
ideas in support of "an ethics of rapacity and greed" (p. 47; the
words belong to the sociologist Erville Woods) -- a development that,
as we have noted, Marx foresaw -- led to a reaction among social
scientists, particularly sociologists, who sought to purge their
disciplines of all traces of biological causality. Talcott Parsons
plays a malign role in Hodgson's story. Parsons, who wanted to carve
out a secure and influential professional niche for sociology,
strategically broadened the definition of Social Darwinism to
encompass "anyone who applied biological ideas in the social
sciences" (p. 54). He then distorted the views of those who fell
within the definition, demonized the distorted views, and erected a
barrier between the social sciences and biology.
Hodgson makes a persuasive case that the history of the term "Social
Darwinism," in particular its transformation into an epithet,
contributed to the disappearance of biological reasoning from the
social sciences. But a few loose ends remain. For a start, Hodgson
doesn't explain why Parsons thought a full-throttle attack on Social
Darwinism would advance the professional interests of sociologists.
Nor is it clear how Veblen and the American institutionalists fit
into the argument. They recognized the evolutionary character of
social phenomena, were never tarred with the Social Darwinist brush,
and were an influential presence in American economics into the
1950s, long after Parson's crusade had succeeded in marginalizing the
ideas of Spencer and Sumner. The near-demise the Veblenian tradition
owes little to the assault on biological approaches that Hodgson
describes. In economics the dominant metaphors had, from early on,
been drawn mainly from physics. The institutionalists showed that a
"biological" outlook might be more appropriate for understanding a
large class of human activities; but they were swimming against the
current.
In Chapter 4 Hodgson elaborates his critique of Marx. The charge that
Marx's theory is teleological is here connected to another criticism
-- that he lacks an adequate theory of human agency, of why people
behave as they do. While a Marxian theory of agency would be useful
to have (and a good deal of work, ignored by Hodgson, has been done
in that direction), the fact that Marx did not himself provide one
doesn't invalidate his general approach. Marx was primarily
interested in how the system as a whole reproduces and evolves, and
at that level of analysis, some degree of abstraction about
individual behavior is not only permissible but necessary. To be
sure, class interests and material conditions do not compel people to
behave in ways that bring about some inevitable path of social
development. Marx knew this, even if he was confident that capitalism
would eventually collapse under the weight of its internal
contradictions. He knew too, though, that those material conditions
have ramifications for what people believe about the world, for how
they make choices, and consequently for how society evolves.
Hodgson's remarks on these matters were initially made in 2001, as
the opening contribution to a debate with Alex Callinicos, whose
rebuttal, presented here as the second part of the chapter, makes
short work of Hodgson's caricature of Marx's views.
The book loses its thematic focus after Part 1. Readers looking to
find direct engagement with the ideas of Darwin and Marx can put the
book aside once they have gotten through Chapter 4. Darwin recedes
into the background, and Marx receives no attention at all after
Chapter 6. This is not to say that the remaining sections of the book
lack interest.
In Part 2 Hodgson scores some hits against the critical realist
school. He begins by dismantling the claim often made by critical
realists that their methodological tenets support an emancipatory
left-of-center politics. He then moves on in Chapter 6 to critique
several concrete analytical applications of critical realism -- its
utilization in defense of Marx's theory of the tendency of the profit
rate to fall; and the attempt to explain Britain's late-twentieth
century industrial decline as the result of trade union resistance to
technological change and workplace reorganization. In these chapters
Hodgson delivers a penetrating dissection of critical realism's
vulnerabilities, though the effect is marred by the occasional cheap
shot, as when he writes that critical realism "is a means for Marxist
academics to make political postures while simultaneously earning
their crust doing serious academic work" (p. 93).
Chapter 7 is an insightful assessment of "The Problem of Formalism in
Economics." Hodgson identifies two extreme positions on mathematical
formalism: (1) rejection of formalism out-of-hand, a view which is
close to the critical realist stance; and (2) the treatment of
formalism, in itself, as the criterion of scientific legitimacy,
without due regard to whether the formal techniques utilized in a
particular argument cast light on the real world -- an attitude that
is all too evident in modern economics. Hodgson advocates a
middle-of-the-road approach: formalism can be useful if we are
attentive to the interpretative context in which any given formal
model is developed and applied. This sensible view, however, then
raises the question, left unaddressed by Hodgson, of what other
criteria are necessary to gauge the usefulness of a model.
The third part of the book is concerned mainly with taxonomic issues:
how are institutions, habits, rules, routines, customs and norms
different from one another, and how are they connected? Much of the
ground covered here is familiar, and there is a good deal of
hair-splitting on display. These chapters flunk the MEGO test ("My
Eyes Glazed Over").
Hodgson has less to say than one might expect about how new
institutions originate, or why they take this or that particular
form. Marx provides a potential answer to such questions, but Hodgson
consigned Marx to the dustbin of history in Part 1, and wants to
leave him there. When, in Chapter 10, Hodgson does take a stab at the
problem of how institutions and rules come into existence, his
analysis lets us down. With coauthor Thorbj?rn Knudsen, he approaches
the issue via a technical exercise that has become common in the new
institutionalist literature, a game-theoretic computer simulation
aimed at showing how a particular rule -- in this case, the
convention about whether cars are to be driven on the left or right
side of the road -- might emerge from the undirected choices of
atomistic agents. It is a curious exercise for Hodgson to undertake
because it seems to be fundamentally at odds with the "old
institutionalist" injunction not to treat social actors as atomistic
entities. If institutions really do matter, our default setting ought
to be skepticism toward any attempt to explain even a simple rule in
terms of a model that abstracts from social and political context.
Hodgson's simulation results undermine the view that habits must be
grounded in given individual preferences; but I'm not sure we need
this sort of analysis to tell us there's something fishy about the
crude reductionism of utility-maximization models. That the
convention under examination involves no issue of conflict also
limits its interest.
The book's central message is that "Explanations of socio-economic
phenomena [ought not to be] reduced ... to individuals [or] to
institutions alone" (p. 201). Few would disagree. In elaborating this
message, Hodgson overstates the differences between his own
methodological approach and Marx's; herein lies the book's principal
flaw. Hodgson presents Darwin and Marx as mutually exclusive
alternatives, when they are in many respects complementary to one
another. Darwinian evolution is indeed "random" in a way that Marx's
capitalist dynamics are not. There's a good reason for this. Social
systems are different from biological systems, and the Darwinian
metaphor can carry us only so far. One has the impression that
Hodgson wants to shield institutionalism from being tarnished by too
close an association with Marxism. Yet his perceptive and careful
reflections on social transformation would be considerably enriched
by a more liberal assimilation of Marxian insights.
Gary Mongiovi teaches economics at St John's University. He and Steve
Pressman co-edit _The Review of Political Economy_.
Copyright (c) 2008 by EH.Net. All rights reserved. This work may be
copied for non-profit educational uses if proper credit is given to
the author and the list. For other permission, please contact the
EH.Net Administrator ([log in to unmask]; Telephone: 513-529-2229).
Published by EH.Net (March 2008). All EH.Net reviews are archived at
http://www.eh.net/BookReview.
-------------- FOOTER TO EH.NET BOOK REVIEW --------------
EH.Net-Review mailing list
[log in to unmask]
http://eh.net/mailman/listinfo/eh.net-review
|