SHOE Archives

Societies for the History of Economics

SHOE@YORKU.CA

Options: Use Forum View

Use Monospaced Font
Show Text Part by Default
Show All Mail Headers

Message: [<< First] [< Prev] [Next >] [Last >>]
Topic: [<< First] [< Prev] [Next >] [Last >>]
Author: [<< First] [< Prev] [Next >] [Last >>]

Print Reply
Subject:
From:
[log in to unmask] (John Medaille)
Date:
Fri Dec 29 15:19:49 2006
Content-Type:
text/plain
Parts/Attachments:
text/plain (96 lines)
Sumitra Shah wrote:  
  
>He called the a posteriori method of "great   
>value in moral sciences, namely, not  
>as means of discovering truth, but of verifying it, and reducing to the lowest  
>point the uncertainty....arising from the   
>complexity of every particular case."  
>Mill made the behavioral  assumptions of: 1) desire for wealth, 2) aversion to  
>labor and 3) present enjoyment of costly indulgences as suitable for what he  
>termed the economic department of life. And he   
>was meticulous in recognizing the  
>cultural difference among groups of people when   
>he wrote about the complexity of  
>social phenomena and "disturbing causes". Too bad the trajectory of economics  
>since his contributions took the formalist,   
>deductive path and ignored some of his  
>most valuable ideas.  
  
  
You do well to cite Mill in this regard, and   
could have, with equal validity, cited any one of   
the 19th century encyclopaedists, who believed   
that all knowledge, including the knowledge of   
ethics, could be brought under the domain of   
"positive science" (whatever that is). But as a   
practical matter, it won't work. As evidence of   
this, take the following "ethical" proposition,   
one that has great economic import:  
  
"God (or nature) has decreed that a few men shall   
be masters and the mass of men shall be servants, serfs, or slaves."  
  
Now, vast amounts of evidence could be adduced   
both for and against this proposition. It was   
certainly a widely held view throughout history   
and, if practice be taken as evidence of belief,   
it is still widely held today, or at least some   
version of it. But regardless of how one comes   
down on the issue, there are only two fundamental   
attitudes towards it, only two types of   
"evidence." On the one hand, one will regard it   
as a question of economic science, and judge it   
true or false on the basis of some set of   
"natural laws," laws viewed as impervious to   
ethics as would be a discussion on the orbit of   
Venus. Or else one will judge it true or false on   
the basis of some ethical content, which content   
is determined by the "natural law" of human   
flourishing, that is, by the ends and purposes of   
human beings and their societies. Both sides,   
note, will invoke "natural law," but will mean   
something entirely different and incompatible.  
  
The result is that those from one fundamental   
attitude will have no way of convincing, or even   
talking to, those who hold the opposite attitude.   
The two views are simply incommensurable, and no   
third set of terms, common to both views and by   
which both views could be judged and compared,   
can be found. But it gets worse. Even within the   
fundamental attitudes, incommensurate views will   
be found. This is especially true of the   
"positivist" view, where it will always turn out   
that different statements will be made axiomatic   
(since that is the word du jour), and these   
axioms will only permit certain kinds of evidence   
to be introduced, evidence that will be entirely   
different for different axioms. So even within   
the confines of the positivist view, you run the   
danger of having not a dialogue but a pure   
cacophony. This danger also exists within the   
ethical attitude, but is somewhat mitigated by   
the realization from the beginning that what is   
being compared is beliefs about man and his end,   
and so there is at least agreement that the argument is teleological.  
  
To take another issue, one you actually brought   
up, Mill (following Hume) takes it as axiomatic   
that man is averse to work. But is this really   
true? Indeed, the evidence would seem to be on   
the other side: when a man gets home from work,   
he starts working on his hobby. What Hume and   
Mill are more likely noting is that man is averse   
to toil (the resistance nature offers to our   
efforts) and to the degrading and dehumanizing   
work that is found in many work places,   
particularly in the day of Mill's mills. But left   
to his own devices, man will find something to   
do; only with the arrival of television do we see   
the emergence of the couch potato as a social   
norm. So, has Mill located a real economic axiom?   
Or are alternative views possible?  
  
  
John C. Medaille  

ATOM RSS1 RSS2