------------ EH.NET BOOK REVIEW --------------
Published by EH.NET (March 2007)
Luigino Bruni, _Civil Happiness: Economics and Human Flourishing in
Historical Perspective_. New York: Routledge, 2006. xv + 169 pp. $135
(hardcover), ISBN: 0-415-32628-1.
Reviewed for EH.NET by Edd Noell, Department of Economics, Westmont College
Economists, along with psychologists, sociologists, and
neuroscientists, are at the forefront of modern research on happiness
(Layard, 2005). Over the past three decades economists have been
wrestling with the quandary posed by Easterlin's Paradox, namely that
individuals do not report an increasing level of happiness despite
increases in personal income over time. Through an analysis of
developments in the history of thought on "economics and human
flourishing," Luigino Bruni's _Civil Happiness_ finds that mainstream
economics has lost its reliance on the civil happiness tradition and
thus is ironically ill-equipped to explain the paradox. Bruni, an
Associate Professor of Economics at the Universita degli Studi di
Milano Bicocca in Italy, claims that happiness invariably involves
interpersonal relationships yet this consideration is excluded by
economics. While there is some hope in the work of behavioral
economists, for the most part modern economics lacks the
methodological tools to appreciate the role of sociality as a source
of happiness. Bruni suggests that economics will be better served by
appreciating the insight that happiness understood in a civil sense
does not necessarily rise and fall with changing income levels.
Why and when did economics lose sight of the interpersonal dimension
of happiness? Bruni points to Adam Smith and Antonio Genovesi as
crucial figures in the late eighteenth century who took similar yet
fundamentally different approaches to addressing happiness in the
emerging market society. Smith's approach of treating economic
relations instrumentally was employed by "the Cambridge civil
tradition" of Malthus and Marshall in the nineteenth century (pp.
88-89). In the same era Bentham's utilitarianism shaped a hedonist
approach to economics which eventually reduced happiness to pleasure
in the works of Jevons. By the twentieth century the influence of
Wicksteed and Pareto had eliminated even this subjectivist approach
to happiness, excluding civil happiness from legitimate
consideration. The eleven chapters of Bruni's book examine both
well-known and somewhat overlooked primary works in the history of
economic thought to describe the manner in which this banishment
occurred and the consequences of these developments for "happiness"
as understood in modern economics.
In the first three chapters Bruni sets out to demonstrate the
deficiencies of economics' understanding of happiness and the
consequent shortcomings of current explanations of Easterlin's
Paradox. Bruni highlights the direct relationship "between individual
well-being and sociality-as-relationality" found in ancient Greek
philosophy but absent in the mainstream literature of economics (p.
17). Distinguishing between hedonism and Aristotle's eudaimonism, he
affirms the latter concept as superior in that it provides an ethical
approach to happiness by seeing it as the realization of an
individual's potential. Aristotle proclaims that wealth, health and
other goods are merely means for achieving eudaimonia (classical
happiness), which is only achieved indirectly through the practice of
relational virtues of intrinsic value such as friendship and
participation in civic life. After being supplanted by Neo-Platonism
for over a thousand years, eudaimonia was revived in the form of
civic humanism during the Renaissance. Civic humanists describe man
as a "civil animal" pursuing civic virtue. However, the bitter civil
strife in Europe generated reflection on a different view of human
nature, dubbed by Bruni the "uncivil animal" tradition and
represented by Machiavelli, Hobbes, Mandeville, and Hume. Each have
in common "an asocial and selfish anthropology" (p. 39).
One of the particularly strong contributions of the book is Bruni's
discussion in chapters 4-6 of the lesser known eighteenth-century
Italian Public Happiness tradition and its attempted reconciliation
of the civil and uncivil perspectives on human nature. Misunderstood
as a concept imported from the French Enlightenment, the notion of
"public happiness" instead stems from the natural law tradition of
Scholasticism and Civic Humanism. A key element in this tradition is
that "there is no happiness outside society and there is no society
without civil virtues and intentional love for the public good" (p.
42). Genovesi is most significant here as a leader of the Neapolitan
School of Civil Economy, which identifies happiness with reciprocity,
in that "happiness and positive interpersonal relationships are ...
two sides of the same coin" (p. 67). The reconciliation of civil and
uncivil perspectives draws on the crucial role of marketplace
reciprocity. Bruni asserts that for Genovesi "engagement in economic
relations is an exercise of civil virtues" (p. 70) because "making
oneself happy doesn't mean impoverishing others, but means making
them rich as you enrich yourself and thus you become happier
together" (p. 76). At the same time Genovesi does not facilely
identify wealth and well-being as identical measures.
In Chapter 7, Bruni turns to the British classical school and finds
both continuities and discontinuities with the Italian school in
understanding civil happiness. Both Smith and Genovesi claim that
"wealth is a means for obtaining the distinction and admiration from
others, upon which our happiness chiefly depends" (p. 80) but wealth
is not an end in itself. Yet Smith does not see "civil virtues as _a
precondition for markets_" (as Genovesi does), but instead depicts
commerce as "the 'creator' of civil virtues" (p. 83, emphasis in the
original). For Smith market relationships don't depend on the classic
relational virtues of friendship, benevolence and/or sympathy. Bruni
acknowledges that Smith views them as "natural sentiments" and
"fundamental features of human beings, just because the human being
is naturally social and needs cooperation to survive." Still, he
states that in Smith's estimation "_the market_ itself doesn't
require them, and works even better without them" (pp. 87-88,
emphasis in original). Instead of Genovesi's approach to sociality in
the market, it is Smith's conception of the market as a place for
instrumental yet civil relationships which shaped nineteenth-century
classical economics.
"The Cambridge civil tradition" is examined in Chapter 8 and is
contrasted in Chapter 9 with a "parallel stream" of thought also
flowing in late eighteenth and nineteenth-century England, Bentham's
Utilitarianism. Here Bruni focuses particularly on the works of
Malthus, Marshall, and J.S. Mill. While Malthus and Marshall
acknowledge that wealth is merely a means to happiness, and that
happiness depends on elements in life such as friendships, leisure,
and religion, they also consider these components of happiness to be
"external" to economics. Malthus finds them "... to be too
ill-defined for inclusion in the economic domain, since economic
analysis needs data and objective measurement ..." (p. 91). At the
same time, Mill's particular recognition of the public, relational
dimension of happiness places him close to the civil economy
tradition and in opposition to Bentham's reduction of happiness to
hedonist utility. Bruni moves on to helpfully discuss the rise and
influence of the hedonist and individualistic version of
utilitarianism. He highlights the manner in which hedonic utility
penetrates neoclassical economics in England (Jevons, Edgeworth) and
Italy (Pantaleoni) so that the meaning of happiness is shrunk and
"all connections with civic virtues" are severed. Bruni observes
"Once Economics broke away from the classical idea of happiness,
happiness became pleasure and Public Happiness became the sum of
individual pleasures" (p. 104).
In Chapter 10 Bruni discusses "the solipsistic foundations of
contemporary Economics" for which even the hedonist approach to
happiness is abandoned. At the turn of the twentieth century, Pareto
and Wicksteed play a key role in excluding "non-instrumental
interpersonal relations"; Bruni makes a convincing case that in their
work we find the reasons for "the passage from happiness/pleasure to
purely instrumental choices without any reference to the psychology
of the subject" (p. 108). Where Pareto drops consideration of motives
and focuses exclusively on rational choice, Wicksteed understands
economics to be "compatible with any motive, including altruism" and
indeed holds that "most non-selfish behaviour is instrumental" (pp.
115, 117). Bruni ends the chapter with a short discussion of two
examples of modern research agendas which continue to rely on an
instrumental framework and exclude interpersonal relationships, i.e.,
game theory and Becker's extension of economic logic to a very wide
range of human behavior.
In the concluding chapter, Bruni names deficiencies in modern
economic methodology yet lauds some recent developments. While many
economists explain "genuine sociality" as a positive externality,
they don't see "family life, friendships, and close relationships"
(p. 122) as relevant for happiness. While they expound positional
theories of happiness, for the most part they don't recognize
relational goods "which cannot be produced, consumed or acquired by a
single individual, because they depend on interaction with others and
are enjoyed only if shared with others" (p. 124). Yet particular
fields of economics are emerging which emphasize the significance of
interpersonal relations. Bruni is hopeful that developments
recognizing the role of "reciprocity, trust, intentions, fairness,
esteem and similar concepts" in both behavioral and experimental
economics indicate "a new season of interest for the interpersonal
dimension" (p. 123).
Historians of economics will likely find in _Civil Happiness_ both
useful insights and certain gaps in the thesis that call for further
explanation. For example, researchers on Smith should benefit from
Bruni's largely careful comparison of the Scottish moral philosopher
and the Italian Genovesi on the market and civil life. Bruni's
observation that the term "happiness" rarely is found in either of
Smith's two major works and his interpretation of Smith's position on
"happiness as deception" could well generate a new line of inquiry
for Smithian scholarship. Yet one wishes that Bruni had more fully
explored the role of sentiments, passions and instincts lying behind
rational decisions which are emphasized by Smith and others prior to
nineteenth-century classical and neoclassical economics. In addition,
Bruni's argument leaves out any sense of why Bentham's identification
of happiness with pleasure is so influential upon Jevons, Edgeworth
and Pantaleoni. Further exploration of the transformation of economic
thinking on motivation and choice with respect to happiness is needed
here; pursuit of the analysis provided by Schabas (2005) on how
economists came to more narrowly depict individuals as rational
utility-maximizing human agents would be particularly helpful.
Nonetheless, _Civil Happiness_ presents an important addition to the
economics literature on happiness through an analysis of the key
turning points in economic thought. Bruni is particularly helpful in
demonstrating the implicit connections between earlier sources in
economics and two quite different facets of modern thought. One is
the work of behavioral and experimental economists which draws on
nineteenth-century utilitarianism; as Bruni notes, "the approach of
the contemporary scholars working on happiness is Benthamite or
Jevonsian, an approach where it is also allowed that people get
happiness/pleasure from social interactions" (p. 118). The other
feature is characteristic of mainstream economics. It relies upon the
"methodological move performed mainly by Pareto and Wicksteed" to
exclude subjectivist considerations and thus "has tremendous
difficulties in understanding the interpersonal matter that is
happiness" (pp. 108, 118). This turn in economic methodology needs to
be reconsidered. Bruni is probably correct in asserting that an
"economic theory more open to genuine sociality could better
understand not only the 'Easterlin paradox' but also those
interactions (that are growing more and more in postmodern market
societies) characterized by the presence of relational goods" (p.
123). _Civil Happiness_ challenges economists not to reify a narrow
concept of happiness but rather re-examine its nature in order to
realize greater progress in our research on a number of substantial
dimensions of civil society.
References:
Richard Layard (2005), _Happiness: Lessons from a New Science_. New
York: Penguin Books.
Margaret Schabas (2005), _The Natural Origins of Economics_. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Edd Noell is Professor of Economics at Westmont College and an editor
of the journal _Faith and Economics_. His current research is
directed towards developments in economic thought on the living wage
in Adam Smith and in early twentieth-century British and American
economics.
Copyright (c) 2007 by EH.Net. All rights reserved. This work may be
copied for non-profit educational uses if proper credit is given to
the author and the list. For other permission, please contact the
EH.Net Administrator ([log in to unmask]; Telephone: 513-529-2229).
Published by EH.Net (March 2007). All EH.Net reviews are archived at
http://www.eh.net/BookReview.
-------------- FOOTER TO EH.NET BOOK REVIEW --------------
EH.Net-Review mailing list
[log in to unmask]
http://eh.net/mailman/listinfo/eh.net-review
|