HES has been quiet for some time, and I was busy when there was a
flurry of discussion about why economists need the history of
economic thought, so I decided to re-ignite the discussion with a
short defense of the following statement: there is a fundamental
difference between the history of economics and the history of
economic thought. Furthermore, while the history of economic
thought is intimately related to economics, the history of
economics is not (in fact, it is more closely related to the
history of science). Those who read Margaret Schabas' article in
HOPE on Breaking Away (1992) will recognize my debt to her
argument.
Before defending this claim, let me say that identifying the
difference between these two disciplines has helped me to
understand a common uneasiness I experience when reading
articles and participating in conferences. The uneasiness I
experience emerges when the assumption is made (either explicitly
or implicitly) that what we are doing is important because it
will enrich the conversation of the economics community. To give
a concrete example, at the Rotterdam conference my paper on
Knight's capital theory was set in a session in which there were
two other papers: a paper on the role of the entrepreneur in the
history of economic thought; and a paper re-examining Knight's
understanding of risk and uncertainty in order to see whether it
could inform a re-orientation of probabilistic thinking in
economics. Both of the other papers were good; my uneasiness had
nothing to do with the quality of the work. Rather, I felt that
my paper served a fundamentally different purpose than the other
two. Some might chalk my uneasiness up to an implicit
"presentism" in the other two papers, but even at the time I
didn't think that. At least one of the papers explicitly
acknowledged the limitations of what the analysis could do given
its starting point. And presentism is present in all our work,
in the sense that we all have contemporary concerns that direct
the questions we ask and the issues we choose to treat. I know
that I have specific issues which drive my research on Knight, and
they are issues which would not have been Knight's.
Now to a defense of my claim that there is a fundamental
difference between the history of economics and the history of
economic thought. The argument could be formulated in several
ways, but the way I am comfortable with is based on a Kuhnian-
type notion of science combined with the notion of separate
discourses. We can begin by identifying what economics is.
Economics is a community of scholars who engage in a disciplined
conversation. The disciplines which direct the conversation are
threefold: a common purpose, common methods, and common agreement
on what constitutes the facts. In order to keep this message as
short as possible, please bear in mind that the conversation is
obviously not as unified as my description suggests. The
community is fraught with disagreement and conflict over its
purpose, its methods, and the facts; but the conflict has not
reached the point where the community splits and separate
conversations operating according to different disciplines emerge
(although that has happened in the past -- the split between
economists and sociologists at the end of the 19th century is one
example). The important point for my thesis is that economics is
a disciplined conversation.
One thing that is important to every discursive community is the
tradition of conversation. Whether it realizes it or not, every
community is constantly engaging its tradition when it engages in
conversation. In some communities, that engagement with
tradition is obvious -- I would suggest that occurs because there
is less agreement and greater conflict over the conversation's
purpose, method, and facts. In other communities, the
commonality of purpose, method and facts renders the
conversation's engagement with its tradition almost transparent.
For examples, consider the differences between physics and
biology; or between archaeology (I'm guessing here) and political
science.
Most of the other social sciences call their conversation's
engagement with its tradition "theory." In economics, we call it
the history of economic thought, reserving the term theory for
the contemporary conversation. But because there is no
conversation without engagement with the tradition, theory and the
history of economic thought are two sides of the same coin.
Underlying both are the purposes, methods, and facts of the
economics community.
So what do I think the history of economics is? Essentially, I
think that the history of economics is a different disciplined
conversation than economics, operating in accordance with a
different purpose, method, and set of facts. The history of
economics is a disciplined conversation about the history of a
different disciplined conversation -- the conversation of
economics. The purposes, methods, and facts that discipline the
history of economics are the purposes, methods, and facts
appropriate to the study of disciplined conversations. [N.B.,
one could mount a counter argument here that would merge
economics and the history of economics by arguing that economic
activity is disciplined conversation -- in a manner similar to
Klamer and McCloskey. That would open up the possibility that
the history of economics can be explained by economics, or that
economics can be explained by discursive theory. Both are
interesting possibilities.]
Anyway, the historian of economics, qua historian, is not
directed by the purposes, methods and facts of the community of
economists. In fact, the existence of the economists' purposes,
methods, and facts may be the very things the historian of
economics wants to explain, according to her methods and for her
purposes. The history of economics and economics are not,
therefore, two sides of the same coin; they are, in fact,
different coins (maybe even different currencies).
Furthermore, historians of economics share more with historians
of other disciplined conversations (we call them historians of
science--understanding science in a broad sense that includes
historians of the humanities, the social sciences, and
communities of non-academic conversation--for example, among
bankers or political figures) than with economists or even
historians of economic thought.
I close with an observation. To say that the history of
economics and the history of economic thought (as part of
economics) are different disciplines does not mean that they
cannot enrich each other. No discursive community exists in
isolation from other communities, and inter-community
(interdisciplinary) dialogue can help each community re-evaluate
its purposes, improve its methods, and establish better facts.
Unfortunately, up to this point historians of economics have
tended to converse more with historians of economic thought and
economic theorists than with historians of science. But that is
changing.
If you have read to this point, what do you think?
Ross
Ross B. Emmett, Augustana Univesity College, Camrose, Alberta
CANADA T4V 2R3 voice: (403) 679-1517 fax: (403) 679-1129
e-mail: [log in to unmask] or [log in to unmask]
|