----------------- HES POSTING -----------------
I just want to echo Lawrence Moss's excellent post. "Endogeneity" and
"exogeneity" are rhetorical conceits -- they are concepts created to help
understand the real world. And the concepts ARE useful. It is a step
beyond making simple correlations, like noting that fat people don't
make as much money as slim people. When I say it that way, it sounds
as if the "direction of causation" -- another formal term -- is going from
being fat to not making money. But ... people with low income tend to
eat food products that are higher in sodium and fat, and tend not to get
enough physical exercise (paradoxically, as in bygone centuries it used
to be the other way around). So now where is the direction of
causation? If you have a statistic that links obesity to low incomes, are
you finding that people who are obese have trouble getting higher
paying jobs, or are you finding that people with low incomes tend to
become obese?
That's when you go to the next step and try to set up a "model" of the
situation -- to specify a line of causation.
But it becomes a human choice to decide what is "endogenous" to the
model and what is "exogenous". And when making that decision -- if
you are not careful -- you have DECIDED the line of causation already.
If I set the model up so that obesity is an EXOGENOUS variable and
income is the ENDOGENOUS variable, then if I am not very careful in
how I set the model up (with other variables that contribute to income
variation) I have committed the same tautology that I would have just
using a simple correlation. I will have CREATED the "proof" of
causation simply by assuming from the beginning what is THERE in
the first place, and what is then the PRODUCT -- I have DECIDED
what is the cause and what is the effect.
The whole concept of exogenous and endogenous variables, everything
that is trying to be done in this sort of effort, is associated with
Marshall because he was really the first (I think) to incorporate INTO a
best-selling textbook, and INTO a highly-regarded teaching program,
the "new" mathematics of physics -- using calculus (and algebra) in a
particular way. (Not really new in terms of years, but "new" in the sense
of its use in the history of economic ideas).
If you are going to explain economic behavior in the real world using
two-dimensional graphs drawn onto a blackboard or printed in a
textbook -- two of the four major methods of dissiminating new
information in the university system (the others being verbal lectures
and laboratory experiments) -- then the concept of exogeneity and
endogeneity become more than a "rhetorical conceit" -- an idea that
helps explain things -- it also becomes a "heuristic device" -- a teaching
tool.
I say that because although economic research has gotten way beyond
two dimensions, students are still introduced into economists via two-
dimensional diagrams and two-dimensional thinking: via the heuristic
device of algebra, and then calculus. (The use of "vectors" has had its
own results -- some of which I find most unfortunate, enabling the
researcher to "pretend" that clumsy variables don't exist because it all
folds into the matrix, so reality can look a lot cleaner than we OUGHT
to know it really is when we are using such complex models -- hope
that made sense!).
Both algebra and calculus require a left and a right side of the equation.
And this is where you get the need for ONE type of variable (on the
right side of the equation) and a DIFFERENT type of a variable (on the
left side of the equation).
Mathematicians tend to go ballistic when they see the basic two-
dimensional price and quantity equations that economists draw on
blackboards to teach freshmen -- because we have our X's and Y's
reversed, you know. But that's a story for a different time.
At any rate, it seems to me that there is just not enough self-awareness
of the degree to which this narrow conceptualization of causation --
while useful -- easily creates the same types of tautologies that we laugh
about when sociologists are using "simple correlation." How do you
know when you are playing with tautology? I think it's when the results
start to diverge GREATLY from the evidence coming in from different
TYPES Of research. Any model that comes out with the result that
"there was no discrimination against women in the nineteenth century
Anglo-American job market" is deliciously counter-intuitive to many
economics -- and ridiculously out-to-lunch to everybody else who does
research in this area. Rather by definition, if the people doing the hiring
are quite up-front about the discrimination, then how on earth can a
simple model prove that they're wrong? ??? I'm waiting for the
person to derive a model that says slavery never happened ...
So where am I headed with this? Well, it seems to me that today
economic THEORY no longer requires such a strict separation of
exogeneity and endogeneity -- which is a good thing, because in the real
world you get feedbacks and iterative processes and codetermination
and all sorts of complications that make it impossible to designate
something completely exogenous or endogenous, ever.
Our use of math to conceptualize reality has gone past algebra and
calculus and nineteenth century physics.
BUT -- to a large degree, the economist's use of modeling HASN't, and
the economist's teaching methods haven't either.
And this is where Marshall comes in again. (I am leaning HEAVILY
here on the British historians of economic thought who have written
about this, BTW -- I didn't come up with this all by myself!) -- it is not
that Marshall instituted the practice, or popularized the notion, of
models that have one exogenous and one or many endogenous
variables -- what he popularized was the concept of "catallectics" (the
spelling is certainly wrong here) -- not that this was a POSSIBLE way
to analyze economic problems, but that it was the ONLY way -- that
we had to stick with models that could use observable variables (like
price and quantity) so we could "prove" or "disprove" this or that
theory about economics.
Everybody learned their Popper pretty well, so we all know we are
supposed to set the model up to "disprove" whatever it is we want to
disprove to prove whatever we want to prove. Then Samuelson (I
believe) pretty much nailed down the whole requirement that only
observable phenomena counted (in his first textbook) -- and combining
all that with statistics and you get econometrics, which is where you
will find the currently used definitions of exogenous and endogenous --
again, rhetorical conceits designed to "fit" a problem into something
that can be "modeled" using econometrics, and then we can
comfortably say we have an "answer."
The problem with all this (I believe) is that our conceptualization of
economics is mathematically too advanced to fit the requirements of
equations with a left and a right side.
For the past 40 years (my timing could be off, but this is what it looks
like to me) there's been an increasing divergence WITHIN economics
between what economists SAY they are doing with models and what
they are actually doing, what they SAY they are doing with mathematics
and what they are actually doing, what they SAY they are doing with
theory and how theory and reality intersects.
And it seems to me that THIS is a problem for historians of economic
thought.
So ... going beyond the initial valid query, (and if you have made it to
the bottom of this overlong message, for which I apologize) -- what
does the history of economic thought have to say about the statement I
just made? When Marshall wrote, there was a unity among the level of
mathematics he used, the type of models he created, the sorts of
problems he addressed, and the state of the scholarly literature at the
time. (Catallectics was definitely an improvement over economic
theories based on "national character" or genetic variations in "race" . .
. )
But that's just not so today. And the intellectual dilemma that has
created has been a problem within economics as a profession -- I am
suggesting -- since about the end of the 1950s, when economists began
writing seriously about microeconomic topics that could not be solved
with reference only to "prices" and "quantities" -- but have continued
to use tools created to serve a type of economics BASED on the
esssential significance of only those two types of variables.
Mary Schweitzer
------------ FOOTER TO HES POSTING ------------
For information, send the message "info HES" to [log in to unmask]
|