SHOE Archives

Societies for the History of Economics

SHOE@YORKU.CA

Options: Use Forum View

Use Monospaced Font
Show Text Part by Default
Condense Mail Headers

Message: [<< First] [< Prev] [Next >] [Last >>]
Topic: [<< First] [< Prev] [Next >] [Last >>]
Author: [<< First] [< Prev] [Next >] [Last >>]

Print Reply
Date:
Fri Mar 31 17:18:33 2006
Message-ID:
<v03007801af06ffd06591@[129.74.251.140]>
Subject:
From:
[log in to unmask] (Wade Hands)
Parts/Attachments:
text/plain (221 lines)
================= HES POSTING ================= 
 
SSK as a Resource for the History of Economic Thought 
 
D. Wade Hands 
Department of Economics 
University of Puget Sound 
 
        I want to focus on the question of using the sociology of 
scientific knowledge (SSK) as a resource for the history of economic 
thought.  Should we do, or what would it mean to do, the history of 
economic thought "in the same way" that "they" (those writing in SSK) do 
the history of natural science?  In a sense this question relates to all 
three of the earlier guest editorials.  Jim Henderson explicitly endorsed 
the SSK approach, and while neither Roy Weintraub nor Phil Mirowski 
explicitly discussed SSK in their editorials, their own work certainly 
demonstrates its influence (e.g. Mirowski 1992 and 1994, Weintraub 1991, 
Weintraub and Mirowski 1994).  Although my remarks will bear directly on 
the questions of whether we should apply SSK and/or what it would mean to 
do so, my approach will be indirect.  I will simply offer "seven points" -- 
seven points that are quite relevant to the question of applying SSK to the 
history of economic thought, but seven points that I do not think have been 
given sufficient attention in the existing literature (by either supporters 
or critics). 
        I will assume quite a bit of familiarity with SSK.  For those 
interested in a more general introduction I would recommend classics such 
as Bloor (1991), Collins (1985), Knorr Cetina (1981), Latour and Woolgar 
(1986) or Shapin and Schaffer (1985); some of the influential collections 
such as Jasanoff, Markle, Peterson and Pinch (1995), Knorr Cetina and 
Mulkay (1983), or Pickering (1992); and for various contact points with 
economics, Coats (1993a, 1993b), Collins (1991), Davis (1997), Hands 
(1994a, 1994b), Knorr Cetina (1991), Maeki (1992), and McClellan (1996) in 
addition to the above works by Mirowski and Weintraub.  The order in which 
the seven points are presented does not reflect their relative importance 
(I am not certain that I even have a stable attitude about their relative 
importance). 
        1.  SSK is less radical when applied to a social science like 
economics than when applied to natural science.  SSK says that "scientists' 
beliefs are caused by social factors."  Well, of course economists' beliefs 
are caused by social factors; they are caused by social factors like the 
observed rate of unemployment or the rate of growth in the money supply. 
SSK says society, not nature, causes the beliefs of scientists; since "the 
economy" is social, not natural, it is hardly surprising (or very radical) 
to say that the beliefs of economists have social causes.  In the case of 
economics, an SSK-inspired history would point to things that were 
traditionally considered to be the "wrong kind" of social factors (like the 
social interests served) rather than to things that were traditionally 
considered to be the "right kind" of social factors (like rates of 
unemployment and inflation).  While such an SSK-inspired study would retain 
some of its debunking tone, almost everyone, including practicing 
economists, would admit that it is far easier (for even the epistemically 
well-intentioned) to slip from the "right social" to the "wrong social," 
than to slip from "nature" to "society."  This may make SSK-inspired 
studies in economics more acceptable to a wider audience than such studies 
in natural science, but it also makes them less radical and potentially 
less interesting. 
        2.  SSK is most powerful when it is juxtaposed against a Whiggish 
historical record.  Or, put alternatively, SSK works best when the existing 
historical literature is thin and self-congratulatory.  Given this, it is 
not surprising that the most successful book-length social constructivist 
work in the history of economic thought focuses on Walrasian general 
equilibrium theory (Weintraub 1991). 
        3.  SSK is not equivalent to "rich, deeply textured, thick 
history."  Most work in SSK is much thicker than the available Whiggish 
alternatives, but "SSK-inspired" is neither necessary nor sufficient for 
"thick."  It is possible to have SSK histories that are relatively thin 
(particularly where the alternative literature denies the presence of any 
social influence), and it is possible to have a thick history that does not 
explicitly involve "the social" as an explanandum (say one based on the 
psychological characteristics of a particular scientist). 
        4.  SSK-inspired history is not identical to the "instantiation of 
historians' values" endorsed in the Weintraub editorial; it is more an 
instantiation of a particular subset of sociologists' values.  Now SSK is 
certainly much closer to the type of work that would reflect historians' 
values than the standard Whiggish history, but they are not exactly the 
same.  SSK focuses on the social determinants of scientific belief; studies 
in the history of science that reflect the traditional values of the 
history profession would certainly include such social factors, but they 
might also include other things as well. 
        5.  SSK is not "discourse analysis" (or in economics, the 
"rhetorical" approach).  There was a time in science studies when the 
sociological approach (SSK) and discourse analysis (studies based on the 
way that scientists organized their talk) appeared to be intertwined 
(Mulkay, Potter, and Yearley 1983, Gilbert and Mulkay 1984), but that time 
seems to have passed.  Now most of those writing in SSK (including some 
one-time supporters of discourse analysis) would say that "discourse 
analysis has been largely abandoned within SSK" (Collins and Yearley, 1992, 
p. 305). 
        6.  SSK has both contributed to and benefited from the general 
anti-foundationalist and anti-essentialist trends in late twentieth century 
intellectual life.  One should be wary of viewing SSK as a new type of 
foundationalism: as the one true universal path to our knowledge about 
knowledge.  Most of those doing SSK-inspired work in the history of 
economics are rather careful about this, but it is important to keep in 
mind that deprivileging nature need not imply reprivileging society (or 
some particular aspect of society).  As Collins and Yearley recently put 
it, we are not in the position to claim that SSK has "touched bedrock" 
(Collins and Yearley, 1992, p. 304). 
        7.  SSK is becoming the site for the re-emergence of long standing 
debates within the philosophy of social science.  A functionalist will do a 
different kind of SSK than a Marxist or a rational choice theorist.  There 
are many different approaches within SSK and the differences can often be 
traced to long-standing debates about which social factors are, or should 
be, the relevant factors in a good social explanation.  During the time 
when the emphasis was on "SSK versus the philosophy of science" and/or "SSK 
versus the views of the scientists themselves" the presence of a common 
enemy helped to blur these differences, but now that SSK has become a 
viable independent discipline the old debates have started to re-emerge. 
Again quoting Collins and Yearley, "epistemological problems are not 
resolved by empirical discoveries" (Collins and Yearley, 1992, p. 303). 
This becomes an important issue in the history of economic thought where 
the social theories employed in the study are often conditioned by the 
economic views being investigated. 
        In closing I want to make it clear that none of these seven points 
are being offered as a critique of the use of SSK as a resource in the 
history of economic thought.  I personally think it is a very useful and 
under-employed resource -- I have used it myself (Hands 1994a, 1994b; Hands 
and Mirowski 1997) and will certainly do so in the future.  My argument is 
only that we need to be clear about what SSK is and what it is not, and to 
be aware of the many roads already traveled by sociologists.  It is my 
(minority) view that a decade or so ago when we were "applying" the work of 
various philosophers of science to the history of economic thought (Popper, 
Lakatos, etc.) we did a very poor job with the relevant texts; I do not 
want to see this repeated with SSK. 
 
REFERENCES 
 
Bloor, David (1991), Knowledge and Social Imagery, 2nd edition, Chicago: 
University of Chicago Press. 
 
Coats, A. W. (1993a), "The Sociology of Knowledge and the History of 
Economics," in The Sociology and Professionalization of Economics: British 
and American Economic Essays, Vol II. London: Routledge, 11-36. 
 
Coats, A. W. (1993b), "The Sociology of Science: Its Application to 
Economics," in The Sociology and Professionalization of Economics: British 
and American Economic Essays, Vol II. London: Routledge, 37-57. 
 
Collins, Harry M. (1985), Changing Order: Replication and Induction in 
Scientific Practice. Beverly Hills, CA: SAGE. 
 
Collins, Harry M. (1991), "The Meaning of Replication and the Science of 
Economics," History of Political Economy, 23, 123-42. 
 
Collins, Harry M. and Steven Yearley (1992), "Epistemological Chicken," in 
Science as Practice and Culture, A. Pickering (ed.), Chicago: University of 
Chicago Press, 301-26. 
 
Davis, John B. (1997), "New Economics and its History: A Pickeringian 
View," in New Economics and Its Writing. Durham, NC: Duke University Press 
[forthcoming]. 
 
Gilbert, G. Nigel and Mulkay, Michael (1984), Opening Pandora's Box: A 
Sociological Analysis of Scientists' Discourse. Cambridge: Cambridge 
University Press. 
 
Hands, D. Wade (1994a), "The Sociology of Scientific Knowledge: Some 
Thoughts on the Possibilities," in New Directions in Economic Methodology, 
R. E. Backhouse (ed.), London: Routledge, 75-106. 
 
Hands, D. Wade (1994b), "Restabilizing Dynamics: Construction and 
Constraint in the History of Walrasian Stability Theory," Economics and 
Philosophy, 10, 243-83. 
 
Hands, D. Wade and Mirowski, Philip (1997), "Harold Hotelling and the 
Neoclassical Dream," in Economics and Methodology: Crossing Boundaries, R. 
Backhouse, D. Hausman, U. Maeki, and A. Salanti (eds.), London: Macmillan 
[forthcoming]. 
 
Jasanoff, Sheila; Markle, Gerald E.; Peterson, James C.; and Pinch, Trevor 
(eds.) (1995), Handbook of Science and Technology Studies. Thousand Oaks, 
CA: SAGE. 
 
Knorr Cetina, Karin (1981), The Manufacture of Knowledge: An Essay on the 
Constructivist and Contextual Nature of Science. New York: Pergamon. 
 
Knorr Cetina, Karin (1991), "Epistemic Cultures: Forms of Reason in 
Science," History of Political Economy, 23, 105-22. 
 
Knorr Cetina, Karin and Mulkay, Michael (eds.) (1983), Science Observed: 
Perspectives on the Social Study of Science. Beverly Hills, CA: SAGE. 
 
Latour, Bruno and Woolgar, Steve (1986), Laboratory Life: the Construction 
of Scientific Facts, 2nd ed., Princeton: Princeton University Press. 
 
Maeki, Uskali (1992), "Social Conditioning in Economics," in Post-Popperian 
Methodology of Economics, N. De Marchi (ed.), Boston: Kluwer, 65-104. 
 
McClellan, Chris (1996), "The Economic Consequences of Bruno Latour," 
Social Epistemology, 10, 193-208. 
 
Mirowski, Philip (1992), "Looking for Those Natural Numbers: Dimensionless 
Constants and the Idea of Natural Measurement," Science in Context, 5, 
165-188. 
 
Mirowski, Philip (1994), "A Visible Hand in the Marketplace of Ideas: 
Precision Measurement as Arbitrage," Science in Context, 7, 563-89. 
 
Mulkay, M., Potter, J. and Yearley, S. (1983), "Why an Analysis of 
Scientific Discourse is Needed," in Science Observed: Perspectives on the 
Social Study of Science, K. Knorr Cetina and M. Mulkay (eds.), Beverly 
Hills, CA: SAGE, 171-203. 
 
Pickering, Andrew (ed.) (1992), Science as Practice and Culture. Chicago: 
University of Chicago Press. 
 
Shapin, Steven and Schaffer, Simon (1985), Leviathan and the Air-Pump: 
Hobbes, Boyle, and the Experimental Life. Princeton, NJ: Princeton 
University Press. 
 
Weintraub, E. Roy (1991), Stabilizing Dynamics: Constructing Economic 
Knowledge.  Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 
 
Weintraub, E. Roy and Mirowski, Philip (1994), "The Pure and the Applied: 
Bourbakism Comes to Mathematical Economics," Science in Context, 7, 245-72. 
 
============ FOOTER TO HES POSTING ============ 
For information, send the message "info HES" to [log in to unmask] 
 
 

ATOM RSS1 RSS2